TRANSLATED FROM THE
GERMAN OF DR E. ZELLER
Professor of the University of
Heidelberg
BY
REV. OSWALD J. REICHEL, B.C.L., M.A.
sometime Vice-Principal of Cuddesdon
College
NEW AND REVISED EDITION
LONDON
LONGMANS, GREEN, AND CO.
AND NEW YORK: EAST 16th STREET
1892
IN Plato and Aristotle Greek Philosophy
reached its greatest perfection. In their hands the
Socratic philosophy of conceptions grew into elaborate
systems, which embraced the whole range of
contemporary knowledge, and grouped it from definite
points of view so as to afford a connected view of the
universe. The study of nature was by them supplemented
by careful inquiries into the subject of morals. It
was, moreover, transformed, enlarged, and enriched by
Aristotle. In metaphysics, the foundations for a
philosophical structure were deeply laid, everything
being referred to first principles, in a way which no
previous philosopher had before attempted. A multitude
of phenomena which earlier thinkers had carelessly
passed over, more particularly the phenomena of mental
life, were pressed into the service of research; new
questions were raised; new answers given. New ideas
had penetrated every branch of knowledge. That
idealism in which the Greek mind so beautifully and
lucidly found expression had been set forth by Plato
in brilliant purity, and had been by Aristotle
combined with careful observation. Practice and theory
had brought the dialectical method to the position of
an art. A valuable instrument of thought had been
gained in the scientific use of terms of which
Aristotle was the real originator. Within a few
generations the intellectual treasures of Greece had
been manifoldly increased, both in extent and value.
The heritage received by Socrates from his
predecessors could hardly be recognized as the same in
that which Aristotle left to his successors.
Great as was the progress made by Greek philosophy in
the fourth century before Christ, quite as great were
the difficulties with which it had perpetually to
contend; quite as difficult the problems on the
solution of which it had to labor. Aristotle had
already pointed out the weak points in the system of
Plato, which rendered it impossible for him to accept
that system as satisfactory. From the platform of
later knowledge still further objections might be
raised to it. Even in Aristotle’s own system
inconsistencies on some of the most important points
might be found, concealed under a certain
indefiniteness of expression, but fatal if once
brought to light to the soundness of the whole. For
with all his ingenuity, Aristotle never succeeded in
harmoniously blending all the elements out of which
his system was composed. Thus the divergencies of his
immediate followers from the original Aristotelian
teaching may be accounted for.
Nor were these defects of a kind that could be easily
disposed of. The deeper the inquiry is carried, the
clearer it becomes that they were defects embedded in
the foundations of the systems both of Plato and
Aristotle, and underlying the whole previous range of
philosophic thought. Omitting details and minor
points, they may all be ultimately referred to two:
either to an imperfect knowledge and experience of the
world, or to the overhaste of idealistic philosophy to
draw conclusions. To the former defect may be
attributed the mistakes in natural science into which
Plato and Aristotle fell, and the limited character of
their view of history; to the latter, the Platonic
theory of ideas with all that it involves--the
antithesis of ideas and appearances, of reason and the
senses, of knowledge and ignorance, of the present
world and the world to come--and likewise the
corresponding points in the system of Aristotle; such,
for instance (to name some of the principal ones
only), as the relation of the particular and the
general, of form and matter, of God and the world, of
the theory of final causes and natural explanations,
of the rational and the irrational parts of the soul,
of speculative theory and practice.
Both defects are closely connected. The Greek
philosophers were content with an uncertain and
imperfect knowledge of facts, because they trusted
conceptions too implicitly, and were ignorant of their
origin and worth; and they had this unconditional
trust in the truth of conceptions because the study of
nature was yet in its infancy. Their knowledge of
history was too limited for them to see the difference
between the results of careful observation and those
of ordinary unmethodical experience, to realize the
uncertainty of most of the traditional principles and
the necessity for a stricter method of induction. The
fault common to both Plato and Aristotle lay in
attaching undue prominence to the dialectical method
inherited from Socrates to the neglect of observation,
and in assuming that conceptions expressing the very
essence of things can be deduced in a purely logical
way from current beliefs and the use of language. In
Plato this dialectical exclusiveness appears most
strongly, and finds striking expression in his theory
of recollection. If all conceptions are inherent from
the moment of birth and need only the agency of
sensible things to produce a consciousness of their
existence, it is only legitimate to infer that, to
know the essence of things, we must look within and
not without, and obtain ideas by abstraction from the
mind rather than by induction from experience. It is
equally legitimate to infer that the ideas derived
from the mind are the true standard by which
experience must be judged. Whenever ideas and
experience disagree, instead of regarding ideas as at
fault, we ought to look upon the data of experience as
imperfect, and as inadequately expressing the ideas
which constitute the thing as it really exists. Thus
the whole theory of ideas, and all that it implies, is
seen to be a natural corollary from the Socratic
theory of conceptions. Even those parts of this theory
which seem most incongruous are best explained by
being referred to the principles of the Socratic
process.
From this defective assumption Aristotle is only
partially free. He attempted, it is true, to supply
the defects in the Socratic and Platonic theory of
conceptions by observation of a kind with which
Plato’s experimental knowledge cannot be compared
either for accuracy or extent. With that attempt he
also combined a complete transformation of the
Platonic metaphysics, whereby he secured the same
position for particulars in relation to the universal
that his predecessor had secured for observation in
relation to conceptional knowledge. But Aristotle did
not go far enough. In his theory of knowledge he
cannot wholly discard the assumption that the soul has
its knowledge by a process of development from within,
and is not only endowed with the capacity of thinking,
but possesses also from its birth the substance of
ideas. In his scientific method a critical
investigation of common notions and of idiom--that in
fact which he himself calls proof by probabilities--is
constantly taking the place of strict induction. His
endeavors to harmonize the two antagonistic currents
in Plato’s teaching may have been undertaken in all
sincerity, but the antagonism was too deeply seated to
yield to his efforts. It not only reappears in the
fundamental ideas of his system, but it colors all its
general results. Beginning with the antithesis between
form and matter, it ends in the
contrast between the world and a soul independent of
the world, in the conception of reason as something
above man, never combining with the lower parts of his
nature to form one complete living unity.
Granting that the Socratic philosophy of conceptions
is the source from which these peculiarities are
derived, still that philosophy is itself only the
expression of the character of the nation which
produced it. In an earlier work it has been shown that
the most distinctive feature of Greek life lay in
confounding the outer and the inner worlds, in
ingenuously assuming that the two originally
corresponded, and are still in perfect harmony with
one another. When the whole mental life of a people
bears this impress, it is sure to be reflected in its
philosophy also. Together with the advantages which
accrue from the confusion of the two, philosophy
shares also the disadvantages which unavoidably attend
any theory which ignores the real distinction between
them. The mind only gradually and imperfectly becomes
aware of the distinctive peculiarity of mental life,
of the notion of personality, of the fact that moral
rights and duties are independent of external
circumstances, of the share of the individual will in
creating ideas. It has also less hesitation in
transferring phases of consciousness directly to
things themselves, in regarding the world from ideal
points of view borrowed from the sphere of mind, in
accepting its own notions of things as realities
without testing their actual truth, and even treating
them as more real than the reality of the senses, and
in confounding the critical analysis of a notion with
the experimental investigation of a thing. If the
philosophy of Greece in the time of its greatest
perfection was not free from these defects; if,
further, these defects were the cause of all the
important faults in the systems of Plato and
Aristotle; the creators of these systems and their
immediate successors are not the only ones to blame;
but the whole mental peculiarity of the people is at
fault of which within the province of science these
men were the greatest representatives.
As the faults of the Platonic and Aristotelian systems
are seen to be connected with the general character of
Greek life, it becomes obvious how difficult it must
have been for Greeks to emancipate themselves from
them. To overcome the difficulty nothing short of a
radical breaking away from old lines of thought would
avail. The origin of ideas, the primary meaning of
conceptions, must be inquired into with searching
thoroughness; a sharper distinction must be drawn
between what is supplied from without and what is
supplied from within; the truth of axioms hitherto
received in metaphysics must be more carefully
investigated than had ever been done as yet. The
intellect must accustom itself to an accuracy of
observation, and to a strictness of inductive process,
never before reached in Greece. Experimental sciences
must attain a degree of completeness which it was vain
to hope to reach by the methods and means then in
vogue. The fashion of regarding nature as though it
were a living being which allowed questions as to
facts to be answered by speculations as to final
causes or by the desire of nature to realize beauty,
must be abandoned. Inquiries into a man’s moral nature
and duties must be kept apart from the simple study of
his conduct in relation to natural surroundings, the
disastrous effects which flow from the confusion of
the two being only too apparent in the national type
of the Greeks, in the exclusively political character
of their morality, and in their adherence to slavery.
Before this pass could be reached how much was there
not to alter in the condition and mental habit of
Greece! Could it indeed be expected that a more
vigorous and more scientific method would gain
foothold so long as the tendency to look upon the life
of nature as analogous to the life of man was kept
alive by a religion such as that of Hellas? Or that
moral science would liberate itself from the trammels
of Greek propriety of conduct, whilst in all practical
matters those trammels were in full force? Or that a
clearer distinction would be drawn between what comes
from without and what from within in ideas--a
distinction which we vainly look for in
Aristotle--until a depth and an intensity had been
given to the inner life, and until the rights and
value of the individual as such had obtained a
recognition which it required the combined influence
of Christianity and the peculiar Germanic character to
bring about? The more vividly the national type and
the national conditions surrounding Greek philosophy
are realized, the firmer becomes the conviction, that
to heal its defects--which are apparent even in its
greatest and most brilliant achievements--nothing
short of a revolution in the whole mental tone of
Greece would avail--such as history has seen
accomplished, but not till after many shifts and many
centuries.
On the platform of the ancient life of Greece such a
change could not possibly have come about. It may be
that under more favorable circumstances Greek
philosophy might have further developed along the same
course of purely intellectual inquiry which it had
previously so successfully followed in the hands of
its earlier representatives, more particularly of
Aristotle. What results might in this way have been
attained, we cannot exactly determine. Speculation is,
however, useless. In point of fact, the historical
circumstances under which philosophy had. to grow
cannot be ignored. Philosophy had become what it was
under the influence of those circumstances. The
Socratic theory of conceptions, and Plato’s theory of
ideas, presuppose on the one hand the high culture of
the age of Pericles, and the brilliant career of
Athens and Greece following on the Persian war. They
also presuppose the political degradation and the
moral exhaustion of Greece during and after the
Peloponnesian war. Aristotle, with his high
intellectual culture, despairing of everything direct
and practical, with his wide view of things, his
knowledge of every kind, his system matured and
elaborate, and embracing all the results of previous
inquiry--appears as the child of an age which was
bearing to the grave a great historical epoch, in
which intellectual labor had begun to take the place
of vigorous political action.
The bloom of Greek philosophy was short-lived, but
not more short-lived than the bloom of national life.
The one was dependent on the other, and both were due
to the action of the same causes. The Greeks, with a
high appreciation of freedom, a ready aptitude for
politics, and a genius for artistic creations,
produced within the sphere of politics one result of
its kind unrivaled and unique. They neglected,
however, to lay the foundations wide and deep. Their
political endurance was not equal to their versatility
and restlessness. Communities limited in extent and
simple in arrangement sufficed for them. But how could
such communities include all branches of the Greek
family, and satisfy at once all legitimate
aspirations? It is the same within the department of
science. Prematurely concluding and rashly advancing
from isolated experiences without mediating links to
the most general conceptions, they constructed
theories upon a foundation of limited and imperfect
experience, which it was wholly inadequate to bear.
Whether, and in how far, the intellect of Greece, if
left to itself, might have remedied these defects in a
longer protracted calm of development, is a question
which it is impossible to answer. As a fact, that
intellect was far too intimately bound up with the
political, the moral, and the religious life--in
short, with the whole mental tone and culture of the
people--not to be seriously affected by a change in
any one of them. It lay, too, in the character and
historical progress of that people to have only a
brief period of splendor, and that soon over. At the
time that the philosophy of Greece reached its highest
point in Plato and Aristotle, Greece was in all other
respects in a hopeless state of decline.
Notwithstanding individual attempts to revive it, the
old morality and propriety of conduct had disappeared
since the beginning of the Peloponnesian war. The old
belief in the gods was likewise gone. To the bulk of
the people the rising philosophy with its ethics
afforded no substitute. Art, although carefully
cultivated, failed to come up to the excellence of the
strictly classic period. Political relations became
daily more unsatisfactory. In the fifth century before
Christ the rivalry of Athens and Sparta had ranged the
states of Greece into two groups. In the succeeding
century disunion spread further. The effort made by
Thebes under Epaminondas to found a new leadership
only multiplied parties. Destitute of a political
center of gravity, the Greeks, of their own choice,
drifted into a disgraceful dependence on the conquered
and now declining Persian empire. Persian gold wielded
an influence which Persian arms had been unable to
exercise. The petty jealousies of tiny states and
tribes frittered away in endless local feuds resources
which with unity and leadership might have
accomplished wonders. Civil order declined, and with
it the well-being and martial prowess of the nation
declined also. The growing pursuit of the art of war
as a profession took the decision of battle more and
more out of the hands of free citizens, and placed it
in those of the numerous bands of mercenaries which
are one of the most baneful phenomena of that age, a
sure sign of the decline of freedom, and of the
approach of a military despotism. When by the rise of
the Macedonian power the danger of a military
despotism loomed nearer, patriots in Greece continued
to deceive themselves with the hope that their
self-devotion would avert the danger, but any
unbiased reader of history sees in the failure of
their attempts to avert it the natural and inevitable
result of causes so deeply rooted in the Greek
character and the course of Greek history, that
neither the most heroic exertions of individuals, nor
the united resistance of the divided states, which
came too late, could for one moment have rendered the
final issue doubtful.
By the battle of Chaeronea the doom of Greece was
sealed. Never since then has Greece attained to real
political freedom. All attempts to shake off the
Macedonian supremacy ended in humiliating disasters.
In the subsequent struggles Hellas, and Athens in
particular, were the play-ball of changing rulers,
the continual arena of their warfare. The second half
of the third century was reached before a purely
Grecian power--the Achaean League--was formed, round
which the hopes of the nation rallied, but the attempt
was wholly inadequate to meet the real requirements of
the times. Soon it became apparent that no remedies
were forthcoming to heal the ills from which the
country was suffering. Discord, their old hereditary
failing, rendered it impossible for Greeks to be
independent in foreign relations, or to be united and
settled at home. Their best resources were wasted in
perpetual struggles between Achaeans, Aetolians, and
Spartans. The very individual who led the Achaeans
against the Macedonians in the cause of independence,
called the Macedonians back to the Peloponnesus to
gain their support against Sparta. When the supremacy
of Macedonia was broken by the arms of Rome, a more
avowed dependence on Italian allies succeeded. And
when, in the year B.C., the province of Achaia was
incorporated into the Roman empire, even the shadow of
freedom which up to that time had been assured
departed for ever.
Sad as were the external affairs of Greece at this
period, and marked as was the decline of its
intellectual power, its mental horizon, nevertheless,
extended and its culture became more generally
diffused. The Macedonian ascendancy, which gave the
deathblow to the independence of Greece, also broke
down the barriers which had hitherto separated Greeks
from foreigners. A new world was opened out before
them, and a vast territory offered for their energies
to explore. Greece was brought into manifold contact
with the Eastern nations belonging to the Macedonian
monarchy, whereby it secured for its culture the place
of honor among them, but at the same time became
subject to a slow, but, in the long run, important
back-current of Oriental thought, traces of which
appear in its philosophy a few centuries later. By the
side of the old famed centers of learning in the
mother country of Hellas, new centers arose, suited by
position, inhabitants, and peculiar circumstances to
unite the culture of East and West, and to fuse into
one homogeneous mass the intellectual forces of
different races. Whilst Hellas, by the number of
emigrants who left her shores to settle in Asia and
Egypt, was losing her population and the Greeks in
their ancestral homes were being ousted by foreigners,
they were gaining the most extensive intellectual
conquests at the time over the very nations by and
through whom they had been oppressed.
Chapter II. Character and Chief Features of the
Post-Aristotelian Philosophy.
THE circumstances which have been briefly
sketched in the preceding chapter are of the greatest
importance in their bearing on the character of the
post-Aristotelian philosophy. Greek philosophy, like
Greek art, is the offspring of Greek political
independence. In the whirl of public life every one is
thrown on himself and his own resources. Thereby, and
by the emulation begotten of unlimited competition for
all the good things of life, the Greek had learned to
make full use of his intellect. Consciousness of his
dignity--which a Greek associated far more closely
than we do with the privilege of citizenship--and
independence of the necessity of struggling for daily
food, had taught him independence of mind, and enabled
him to devote himself to the pursuit of knowledge
without any ulterior aim. With the decline of
political independence the mental powers of the nation
were broken past remedy. No longer borne up by a
powerful esprit de corps, weaned from the
habit of working for the common weal, the majority
gave themselves up to the petty interests of private
life and personal affairs. Even the better disposed
were too much occupied in contending against the low
tone and corruption of their times, to be able to
devote themselves in moments of relaxation to
independent speculation. What could be expected in
such an age as that which preceded the rise of the
Stoic and Epicurean systems, but that philosophy would
become practical itself, if indeed it were studied at
all?
An age like that did not require theoretical
knowledge, but it did require moral bracing and
strengthening. If these were not to be had from
popular religion in its then state, was it matter for
wonder that philosophy should be looked to to supply
the deficiency, seeing that in all cultivated circles
philosophy had already taken the place of religion? If
we ask in what form, and in what form only, philosophy
could supply the deficiency under the then
circumstances, the answer is not far to seek. There
was little room for creative effort, plenty for
sustained endurance; little for activity without,
plenty for activity within; little room for public
life, plenty of room for private life. So utterly
hopeless had the public state of Greece become, that
even the few who made it their business to provide a
remedy could only gain for themselves the honor of
martyrdom. As matters stood, the only course open for
the best-intentioned was to withdraw entirely within
themselves, to entrench themselves within the safe
barriers to their inner life against outward
misfortunes, and to make happiness dependent entirely
on their own inward state.
Stoic apathy, Epicurean self-contentment, and Sceptic
imperturbability, were the doctrines which suited the
political helplessness of the age, and they were
therefore the doctrines which met with the most
general acceptance. There was yet another which suited
it--viz., the sinking of national distinctions in the
feeling of a common humanity, the severance of morals
from politics which characterizes the philosophy of
the Alexandrian and Roman period. The barriers which
kept nations apart had been swept away, together with
their national independence: East and West, Greeks and
barbarians, were united in large empires, brought into
communication and forced into comparison with one
another in matters the most important. Philosophy
declared that all men are of one blood and are equally
privileged citizens of one empire, that morality rests
on the relation of man to man, and is independent of
nationality and position in the state; but in so doing
it only explicitly stated a truth which was partly
realized and partly implied in actual life.
The very course which philosophy itself had taken
during the previous century and a half had prepared
the way for the turn which now set in. Socrates and
the Sophists, in different ways no doubt, had each
devoted themselves to the practical side of life; and
thus the Cynic School was the precursor of Stoicism,
the Cyrenaic of Epicureanism. These two Schools are,
however, were only of minor importance in the general
progress of philosophy in the fourth century, and
sophistry by the close of the same century was already
a thing of the past. Socrates, it is true, would have
nothing to do with physical inquiries; yet he felt the
desire for knowledge far too keenly to bear comparison
with the post-Aristotelian philosophers. Proposing to
concern himself only with subjects which were of
practical use in life, he yet put forth a theory of
knowledge which involved a reform quite as much of
speculative as of practical philosophy, and that
reform was accomplished on a grand scale by Plato and
Aristotle.
However little Greek philosophy as a whole developed
during the fourth century along the lines of its
subsequent expansion, still the speculations of Plato
and Aristotle necessarily helped to prepare for the
coming charge. The antagonism between the ideal and
phenomenal worlds which Plato set up, and Aristotle
vainly attempted to bridge over, leads ultimately to a
contrast between the outer and the inner life, between
thought and the object of thought. The generic
conceptions or forms, which Plato and Aristotle regard
as most truly real, are, after all, fabrications of
the human mind. The conception of reason, even in its
expanded form as the divine Reason, or reason of the
world, is an idea formed by abstraction from the inner
life. And what is really meant by identifying form in
itself with what is, and matter with what is possible,
or even (as Plato does) with what is not, or
by placing God outside of and in contrast to the
world, but the admission that man finds in his own
mind a higher and more real existence than any which
he finds outside of it, and that what is truly divine
and unlimited must be in the mind as an idea, apart
from and independent of all impressions from without?
Plato and Aristotle in fact declared that reason
constitutes the real essence of man--reason coming
from above and uniting itself with the body, but in
itself superior to the world of sense and life in
time--and that man’s highest activity is thought,
turned away from all external things, and meditating
only on the inner world of ideas. It was only one step
further in the same direction for the
post-Aristotelian philosophy to contemplate man in
complete severance from the outer world, and to refer
him to himself for that satisfaction winch he can find
nowhere else in life.
This step was taken by the Schools of the Stoics,
Epicureans, and Sceptics which appeared in the first
half of the third century before Christ, superseded
the the influence of the older Schools, and asserted
their supremacy without great variation in their
teaching until the beginning of the first century. In
whatever else these three Schools may differ, at least
they agree in two fundamental points, (1) in
subordinating theory to practice, and (2) in the
peculiar character of their practical philosophy.
The subordination of, theory to practice is most
apparent in the School of Epicurus. It is nearly as
clear in the case of the Sceptics, who. denying all
possibility of knowledge, left as the only ground of
action conviction based on probabilities. Both Schools
also agree in considering philosophy as only a means
for securing happiness. By the Stoics, on the other
hand, the need of philosophic speculation was felt
more strongly; but even in their case it may be seen
that speculation was not pursued simply for its own
sake, but for practical purposes, by which it was also
determined. Thus the Stoics, like the Epicureans, in
the speculative part of their system confined
themselves to current views--thereby showing that the
source of their philosophical peculiarities lay
elsewhere than in speculation, and that other studies
had greater value in their eyes, in which also they
considered themselves more proficient. They even
expressly stated that the study of nature is only
necessary as a help to the study of virtue. It is
beyond question, that their chief peculiarities, and
those which give them an importance in history, are
ethical. The other parts of their system, more
particularly those in which their distinctive tenets
appear, are likewise regulated by practical
considerations. This statement will hereafter be shown
in detail. It may suffice to observe now, that the
most important point in the logic of the Stoics--the
question as to the standard of truth--was decided by a
practical postulate; that the fundamental principles
of the Stoic metaphysics are only intelligible from
the ground of their ethics; that for natural science
the Stoics did very little; that in their theory of
final causes on which they lay so much stress nature
is explained by moral considerations; and that their
natural as well as their positive theology bears ample
testimony to the practical tone of their system.
Standing in advance of the Epicureans by their higher
intellectual training and their learned energy, and in
opposition to the Sceptics by their dogmatism, the
Stoics nevertheless agree with both these Schools in
the essentially practical character of their teaching.
This relationship is more strikingly seen in the way
in which they deal with the practical problem. The
Epicurean imperturbability is akin to that of the
Sceptics; both resemble the Stoic apathy. All three
Schools are agreed that the only way to happiness
consists in peace of mind, and in avoiding all those
disturbances which sometimes arise from external
influences, at other times from internal emotions;
they are only divided as to the means by which peace
of mind may be secured. They are also agreed in making
moral activity independent of external circumstances,
and in separating morals from politics, although only
the Stoics set up the doctrine of the original unity
of the whole human family, and insist on being
citizens of the world. Through all the Schools runs
the common trait of referring everything to the
subject, and constantly falling back on man and his
own inner life, one consequence of which is the
prominence given to action in preference to
speculation, and another that action is determined by
personal certainty, and a mental equilibrium which
must be attained by the exercise of will and the
cultivation of the intellect.
The same character belongs to philosophy in the
centuries succeeding the rise of these three Schools;
during which the circumstances which produced that
character were not materially altered. In addition to
the followers of the old Schools, Eclectics are now
met with, who gather from every system what seems true
and probable. In this process of selection their
guiding principle is regard for the practical wants of
man. Hence the ultimate standard of truth is placed in
personal consciousness. Everything is referred to the
subject as its center. In ethics and natural theology
the Eclectics were mainly indebted to the Stoics. A
new School of Sceptics also arose, not differing in
its tendencies from the older one. Neopythagoreans and
Platonists appeared, not satisfied with human
knowledge, but aspiring to higher revelations.
Professing to appeal to the metaphysics of Plato and
Aristotle, these philosophers betray their connection
with the later post-Aristotelian Schools, not only by
borrowing largely from the Stoics for the material for
their theology and ethics, but also by their general
tone; knowledge is for them less even than for the
Stoics an end in itself, and they are further from
natural science. With them philosophy is subservient
to the interests of religion; its aim is to bring men
into proper relation with God; and the religious needs
of mankind are the highest authority for science.
The same observations apply also to Plotinus and his
successors. These philosophers are not lacking in an
elaborate science of metaphysics. The care which they
devoted to this science leaves no doubt as to their
lively interest in scientific completeness and
systematic arrangement. For all that their speculative
efforts bear the same relation to the practical aim of
philosophy as those of the Stoics, who in point of
learning and logical elaboration of a system are quite
their equals. A real interest in knowledge was no
doubt one of the elements which brought Neoplatonism
into being; but it was not strong enough to
counterbalance another, the practical and religious
sentiment. The mind was not sufficiently independent
to be able to get on without appealing to intellectual
and theological authorities; the scientific procedure
was too mixed to lead to a simple study of things as
they are. As in the case of the Neopythagoreans, the
ultimate ground of the system is a religious want. The
divine world is only a portion of human thought
projected out of the mind, and incapable of being
fully grasped by the understanding. The highest
business of philosophy is to reunite man with the
divine world external to himself. To attain this end,
all the means which science supplies are employed.
Philosophy endeavors to explain the steps by which the
finite gradually came to be separated from the
original infinite being; it seeks to bring about a
return by a regular and systematic course; and in this
attempt the philosophic spirit of Greece, by no means
extinct, proved its powers by a result of its kind
unrivaled In the first instance, no doubt, the problem
was so raised as to press philosophy into the service
of religion; but, in the long run, it became apparent
that, with the premises assumed, a scientific solution
of the religious question was impossible. The idea of
an original being with which the system started was a
reflex of the religious sentiment, and not the result
of scientific research, and the doctrine of a mystical
union with a transcendental being was a religious
postulate, the gratuitous assumption of which betrays
an origin in the mind of the thinker. The platform of
Neoplatonism is the same, therefore, as that of the
other post-Aristotelian systems; and it is hardly
necessary in proof of this position to point to the
agreement of Neoplatonism in other respects with
Stoicism, and especially in ethics. Far the two
systems lie asunder, the one standing at the beginning
the other at the end of the post-Aristotelian
philosophy, nevertheless both display one and the same
attitude of thought; and we pass from one to the other
by a continuous series of intermediate links.
In passing from School to School the
post-Aristotelian philosophy assumed, as might be
expected, various modifications of character in course
of time; nevertheless, it retained a certain mental
habit and certain common elements. Such was the
neglect of intellectual originality, which drove some
thinkers to a skeptical denial of all knowledge, and
induced others to take their knowledge at second hand
from older authorities. Such was the prominence given
to practical over speculative questions. Such was the
disregard for natural science, and, in comparison with
former times, the greater importance attached to
theology, apparent not only in the controversy between
the Epicureans and Stoics, but also in the apologetic
writings of the Stoics and Platonists. Such, too, was
the negative morality which aimed at independence of
the outer world, at mental composure, and philosophic
contentment; the separation of morals from politics;
the moral universalism and citizenship of the world;
the going within self into the depths of the soul, the
will, and the thinking powers; the deepening of the
consciousness accompanied at the same time by a
narrowing and isolation of it, and the loss of a
lively interest in the outer world, and in the simple
scientific study thereof.
This mental habit, first of all, found simple dogmatic
expression in philosophical systems. Not only moral
science, but also logic and natural science, were
treated in a way consonant with it, although they were
partially built upon older views. In dealing with the
moral problem, two Schools come to view, markedly
different and decided in their peculiarities. The
Stoics regard almost exclusively the universal element
in man who seeks contentment within, the Epicureans
catch at the individual side of his being. The Stoics
regard man exclusively as a thinking being, the
Epicureans as a creature of feeling. The Stoics make
happiness to consist in subordination to the law of
the whole, in the suppression of personal feelings and
inclinations, in virtue; the Epicureans in individual
independence of everything external, in the unruffled
serenity of the inner life, in painlessness. The
theoretical bases of their teaching correspond with
these fundamental ethical positions.
Although the rivalry between these two Schools was
great, both, nevertheless, stand on the same platform.
Absolute composure of mind, freedom of the inner life
from all disturbance from without, is the goal at
which both aim, although they follow different
methods. Hence it becomes necessary to insist on the
common element as the essential aim and matter of
philosophy. If the philosophic axioms of the two
systems contradict one another, it may be thence
inferred that the aim of both may be attained
independently of any definite dogmatic view; in short,
knowledge may be despaired of in order to pass from a
recognition of ignorance to a general indifference to
everything and to an unconditional repose of mind.
Thus Skepticism is connected with Stoicism and
Epicureanism, as the third chief form of the
philosophy of that age. Apart from Pyrrho’s School, it
is most effectually represented in the New Academy.
The rise, the growth, and the conflict of these three
Schools, by the side of which the older Schools have
only a subordinate value, occupies the first portion
of the period of post-Aristotelian philosophy, and
extends from the end of the fourth to the beginning of
the first century before Christ. The distinctive
features of this epoch consist partly in the
predominance of the above tendencies, and partly in
their separate existence, without modification by
intermixture. After the middle of the second century a
gradual change may be observed. Greece had then become
a Roman province, and the intellectual intercourse
between Greece and Rome was continually on the
increase. Many learned Greeks resided at Rome,
frequently as the companions of families of high
birth; others living in their own country, were
visited by Roman pupils. Was it possible that in the
face of the clearly-defined and sharply-expressed
Roman character, the power and independence of the
Greek intellect, already unquestionably on the
decline, would assert its ancient supremacy? Or that
Greeks could become the teachers of Romans without
accommodating themselves to their demands, and
experiencing in turn a reflex influence? Even Greek
philosophy could not withdraw itself from this
influence. Its creative power was long since in
abeyance, and in Skepticism it had openly avowed that
it could place no trust in itself. To the practical
sense of a Roman no philosophical system commended
itself which did not make for practical results by the
shortest possible route. To him practical needs were
the ultimate standard of truth. Little did he care for
strict logic and argumentative accuracy in scientific
procedure. Differences of schools, so long as they had
no practical bearing, were for him of no importance.
No wonder that Greek philosophy, touched by the breath
of Rome, lent itself to Eclecticism!
Whilst on the one side of the world the Greeks were
falling under the influence of the nation that had
subdued them, on the other they were assimilating the
views of the Oriental nations whom they had subdued by
martial as well as by mental superiority. For two
centuries, in philosophy at least, Greece had held her
own against Oriental modes of thought. Now that her
intellectual incapacity continually increased, those
modes of thought gained for themselves a foothold in
her philosophy. Alexandria was the place where the
connection of Greece with the East was first and most
completely brought about. In that center of commerce
for all parts of the globe, East and West entered into
a connection more intimate and more lasting than in
any other center. Nor was this connection a mere
accident of circumstances; it was also a work of
political forecast. From its founder, Ptolemy Soter,
the Ptolemaean dynasty inherited as the principle of
government the rule always to combine what is native
with what is foreign, and to clothe new things in the
old and venerable forms of Egyptian custom and
religious ceremony. At Alexandria, accordingly, there
arose, towards the beginning of the first century
before Christ, a School calling itself at first
Platonic, afterwards Pythagorean, which later still,
in the shape of Neoplatonism, gained the ascendancy
over the whole domain of philosophy. The very fact,
however, that such a change in philosophic views did
not appear sooner, is sufficient to show that it was
produced by external circumstances. But
notwithstanding external circumstances it would never
have come about had not the intellect of Greece in the
course of its own development been ripe for it.
The same remark holds good of the rise of that
practical Eclecticism which we have before traced to
the influence of Rome. Even in the period of
intellectual exhaustion, Greek philosophy was not
simply the resultant of its outward surroundings, but,
under the influence of outward surroundings, took
shape in a way indicated by its previous progress. If
the lingering remains of a few small Schools, which
soon expired, are excepted, there existed, after the
beginning of the third century before Christ, only
four great philosophic Schools--the Peripatetic, the
Stoic, the Epicurean, and the School of Platonists.
The last-named of these was converted to Skepticism
by Arcesilaus. These four Schools were all permanently
established at Athens, where a lively interchange of
thought took place between them, which renders a
thorough comparison of their several teachings
comparatively easy. It was only natural that they
would not long exist side by side without making
overtures towards union and agreement. These overtures
were favored by Skepticism, which, denying the
possibility of knowledge, only allowed a choice
between probabilities, and decided that choice by the
standard of practical needs. Hence, towards the close
of the second century before Christ, these philosophic
Schools may be observed to emerge more or less from
their exclusiveness. An eclectic tendency steals over
philosophy, aiming not so much at scientific knowledge
as at attaining certain results for practical use. The
distinctive doctrines of each School drop into the
background; and in the belief that infallibility
resides solely in the mind itself, such portions are
selected from each system as seem most in harmony with
the selecting mind. The germ of this eclectic mode of
thought lay in Skepticism On the other hand,
Eclecticism involves doubt. Hence, soon after the
Christian era, a new school of doubt developed, which
continued until the third century. There was thus, on
the one hand, a lively interest in knowledge, which
was desired in the practical interest of religion and
morals; and, on the other hand, a disbelief in the
truths of existing knowledge, and, indeed, of
knowledge generally, openly avowed by some as
Sceptics, secretly betrayed by others in the
unsettledness of their Eclecticism. These two currents
coalescing, led to the thought that truth, which
cannot be found in knowledge, exists somewhere outside
of it, and must be looked for partly in the religious
traditions of the early days of Greece and the East,
partly in direct divine revelation. Then came in such
a notion of God, and of His relations to the world, as
accords with this belief in revelation. Man knowing
that truth lies outside himself, and doubting his own
capacities to attain it, removes deity, as the
absolute source of truth, into another world; and
because the need of a revelation of truth still
exists, the interval between God and the world is
peopled with intermediate beings, who are sometimes
conceived of as metaphysical entities, and at other
times appear as the demons of popular belief. This
mental habit, which is connected with Plato and
Pythagoras, among the older systems, forms the
transition to Neoplatonism. The appearance of
Neoplatonism introduces the last stage in the
development of Greek philosophy.
Yet even this turn in Greek philosophy was not
uninfluenced by the circumstances of the times. Since
the end of the second century after Christ, the
decline of the Roman Empire progressed apace. Dread of
the dangers which threatened it on all sides, the
pressure of the times and distress made startling
progress. All means of defense hitherto employed had
proved unavailing to stem destruction. With ruin
everywhere impending, the desire and longing for
higher assistance increased. No such assistance was
forthcoming from the old gods of Rome or the religious
faith of the day; despite which circumstances were
daily becoming more hopeless. Then it was that the
desire for foreign forms of worship which had been
gradually spreading over the Roman world since the
last days of the Republic, and which the circumstances
of the Empire had stimulated, gained ground. That
desire was favored by the highest power in the state,
under the Oriental and half Oriental emperors who for
nearly half a century after Septimius Severus occupied
the imperial throne. The state and the gods of the
state were continually losing their hold on the
respect of men. Meanwhile, on the one hand, Oriental
worships, mysteries old and new, and foreign heathen
religions of the most varying kinds, were ever gaining
fresh adherents. On the other, Christianity was
rapidly acquiring a power which enabled it openly to
enter the lists for supremacy among the recognized
religions of the state. The powerful monarchs who
about the middle of the third century attempted to
refound the Empire, had not for their object to
restore a specifically Roman form of government, but
to bring the various elements which composed the
Empire under one sovereign will by fixed forms of
administration. In this attempt Diocletian and
Constantine succeeded. The Roman character asserted
itself, as a ruling and regulating power, but it did
so under the influence of another originally foreign
character. The Empire was a congeries of nations
artificially held together, and arranged on a
carefully-designed plan; its center of gravity lay
not within the nation, but in the simple will of the
prince, himself exalted above all rules and laws of
state, and deciding everything without appeal and
without responsibility.
In like manner Neoplatonism united all the elements of
previous philosophical Schools into one comprehensive
and well-arranged system, in which each class of
existences had its definite place assigned to it. The
initial point in this system, the all-embracing unity,
was a being lying beyond the world, high above every
notion that experience and conception can supply,
unmixed with the process of life going on in the
world, and from his unattainable height causing all
things, but himself subject to no conditions of
causality. Neoplatonism is the intellectual
reproduction of Byzantine Imperialism. As Byzantine
Imperialism combines Oriental despotism with the Roman
idea of the state, so Neoplatonism supplements the
scientific forms of Greek philosophy with Oriental
mysticism.
In Neoplatonism the post-Aristotelian philosophy had
manifestly veered round into its opposite.
Self-dependence and the self-sufficingness of thought
made way for implicit resignation to higher powers,
for a craving for revelation, for an ecstatic
departure from the sphere of conscious mental
activity. Man has abandoned the idea of truth within
for truth to be found only in God. God stands there as
abstract spirituality removed into another world in
contrast to man and the world of appearances.
Speculation has but one aim--to explain the procession
of the finite from the infinite, and the conditions of
its return into the absolute; but neither of these
problems can meet with a satisfactory intellectual
solution. Even this form of thought betrays undeniably
the personal character of the post-Aristotelian
philosophy, and is the natural outcome of previous
teaching, as will be more fully seen in the sequel.
With it the creative powers of the Greek mind were
exhausted. After being driven step by step during
centuries from the platform of their own national
philosophy, the Greeks were eventually entirely
dislodged therefrom by the victory of Christianity.
Neoplatonism made one more futile attempt to rescue
the forms of Greek culture from its mighty rival, but
when that attempt failed Greek religion and Greek
philosophy went down together.
PART II. THE STOICS
CHAPTER III. History of the Stoics until the End of
the Second Century B.C.
A STRIKING feature in the history of the
post-Aristotelian philosophy, and one which at the
same time brings forcibly home the thorough change in
its surroundings, is the fact that so many of its
representatives come from eastern countries in which
Greek and Oriental modes of thought met and mingled.
Although for centuries Athens still continued to have
the reputation of being the chief seat of Greek
philosophy, and did not cease to be one of the most
important seminaries of philosophy, even when it had
to share that reputation with other cities, such as
Alexandria, Rome, Rhodes, and Tarsus, yet at Athens
itself there were teachers not a few whose foreign
extraction indicates the age of Hellenism. This remark
applies primarily to the later Neoplatonic School;
next to it it is of none more true than of the Stoic.
With this fact may be also associated the
world-citizenship of this School, though it would be
unfair to attribute a general characteristic of the
then state of the world to purely external
circumstances. Nearly all the most important Stoics
before the Christian era belong by birth to Asia
Minor, to Syria, and to the islands of the Eastern
Archipelago. Then follow a series of Roman Stoics, by
the side of whom the Phrygian Epictetus occupies a
prominent place; but Greece proper is represented only
by men of third or fourth rate capacity.
The founder of the Stoic School, Zeno by name, was the
son of Mnaseas, and a native of Citium in Cyprus.
Leaving his home, he repaired to Athens, about the
year 320 B.C., where be at first joined the Cynic
Crates. He appears to have soon become disgusted with
the extravagances of the Cynics’ mode of life, and his
keen desire for knowledge could find no satisfaction
in a teaching so meager as theirs. To supply their
defects he had recourse to Stilpo, who united to the
moral teaching of the Cynics the logical acumen of the
Megarians. He also studied under Polemo, and it is
said under Xenocrates and Diodorus the logician, with
whose pupil Philo he was on terms of intimacy. After a
long course of intellectual preparation, he at last
appeared as a teacher, soon after the beginning of the
third, or perhaps during the last years of the fourth
century B.C. From the Stoa, the place which he
selected for delivering his lectures, his followers
derived their name of Stoics, having first been called
after their master Zenonians. Such was the universal
respect inspired by his earnestness, moral strictness,
and simplicity of life, and the dignity, modesty, and
affability of his conduct, that Antigonus Gonatas vied
with the city of Athens in showing appreciation of
him. Although lacking smoothness of style and using a
language far from pure, Zeno had nevertheless an
extensive following. Leading a life of singular
moderation, he reached an advanced age untouched by
disease, although he naturally enjoyed neither robust
health nor an attractive person. A slight injury
having at length befallen him, which be regarded as a
hint of destiny, he put an end to his own life. His
not very numerous writings have been lost, with the
exception of a few fragments, some no doubt dating
from the time when, as a pupil of Crates, he adhered
more strictly to Cynic ideas than was afterwards the
case. This point ought not to be forgotten in
sketching his teaching.
The successor to the chair of Zeno was Cleanthes, a
native of Assos in the Troad, a man of strong and firm
character, of unusual endurance, energy, and
contentment, but also slow of apprehension, and
somewhat heavy in intellect. Resembling Xenocrates in
mind, Cleanthes was in every way adapted to uphold his
master’s teaching, and to recommend it by the moral
weight of his own character, but he was incapable of
expanding it more completely, or of establishing it on
a wider basis.
Besides Cleanthes, the best known among the pupils of
Zeno are Aristo of Chios, and Herillus of Carthage,
who diverged from his teaching in the most opposite
directions, Aristo confining himself rigidly to
Cynicism, Herillus approximating to the leading
positions held by the Peripatetic School.
Other pupils of Zeno were Persteus, a countryman and
companion of Zeno; Aratus, the well-known poet of
Soli; Dionysius of Heraclea in Pontus, who afterwards
joined the Cyrenaic or Epicurean School; and Sphaerus
from the Bosporus, who studied first in the School of
Zeno, and afterwards in that of Cleanthes, and was the
friend and adviser of Cleomenes, the unfortunate
Spartan reformer. Of a few other pupils of Zeno the
names are also known; but nothing beyond their names.
No appreciable addition was made to the Stoic doctrine
by any one of them.
It was therefore fortunate for Stoicism that Cleanthes
was followed in the presidency of the School by a man
of learning and argumentative power like Chrysippus.
In the opinion of the ancients, Chrysippus was the
second founder of Stoicism. Born in the year 280 B.C.,
at Soli in Cilicia, after being a pupil of Cleanthes
and it is said even of Zeno himself, he succeeded, on
the death of Cleanthes, to the conduct of his School.
He is also said to have attended the lectures of
Arcesilaus and Lacydes, philosophers of the Middle
Academy; whose critical methods he so thoroughly
appropriated, that later Stoics accused him of
furnishing Carneades with the necessary weapons for
attacking them, by the masterly manner in which he
raised philosophical doubts without being able to
answer them satisfactorily. This critical acuteness
and skill, more than anything else, entitle him to be
regarded as the second founder of Stoicism. In
learning, too, he was far in advance of his
predecessors, and passed for the most industrious and
learned man of antiquity. Independent in tone, as his
general conduct and intellectual self-reliance often
proved, he deviated from the teaching of Zeno and
Cleanthes, as might be expected, in many respects.
Still, the fundamental principles of the system were
not altered by him; only their intellectual treatment
was perfected and deepened. In fact, the Stoic
doctrine was expanded by him with such completeness in
details, that hardly a gleaning was left for his
successors to gather up. In multitude of writings he
exceeded Epicurus; their titles, and a comparatively
small number of fragments, being all that have come
down to us. With such an extraordinary literary
fertility, it will be easily understood that their
artistic value is not very high. The ancients are
unanimous in complaining of their careless and impure
language, of their dry and often obscure style, of
their prolixity, their endless repetitions, their
frequent and lengthy citations, and their too frequent
appeals to etymologies, authorities, and other
irrelevant proofs. But by Chrysippus the Stoic
teaching was brought to completeness; and when he
died, in the year 206 B.C., the form was in every
respect fixed in which Stoicism would be handed down
for the next following centuries.
A contemporary of Chrysippus, but probably somewhat
his senior, was Teles, from whose writings a few
extracts have been preserved by Stobaeus, in the shape
of popular moral considerations written from a Cynic
or Stoical point of view. The same age also produced
the Cyrenaic Eratosthenes, a man distinguished in
every branch of knowledge, but particularly celebrated
for his mathematical attainments, who was gained for
Stoicism by Aristo. Another contemporary of
Chrysippus, and perhaps his fellow-student, who in
many respects approximated to the teaching of the
Peripatetics, was the Stoic Boethius. The proper
scholars of Chrysippus were without doubt numerous;
but few of their names are known to us. The most
important among them appear to have been Zeno of
Tarsus, and Diogenes of Seleucia, who succeeded
Chrysippus in the presidency of the School. The pupil
and successor of Diogenes, in his turn, was Antipater
of Tarsus, in connection with whom Archedemus his
countryman is frequently mentioned. Under Panaetius,
Antipater’s scholar, Stoicism entered the Roman world,
and there underwent internal changes, to which
attention will be drawn in the sequel.
CHAPTER IV. Authorities for the Stoic Philosophy:
Its Problem and Divisions.
To give a faithful exposition of the Stoic
philosophy is a work of more than ordinary difficulty,
owing to the circumstance that all the writings of the
earlier Stoics, with the exception of a few fragments,
have been lost. Those Stoics whose complete works are
still extant--Seneca, Epictetus, Marcus Aurelius,
Heraclitus, Cornutus--lived under the Roman Empire,
and therefore belong to a time in which all Schools
alike exposed to foreign influences had surrendered or
lost sight of many of their original peculiarities,
and had substituted new elements in their place. The
same remark applies to writers like Cicero, Plutarch,
Diogenes, Sextus Empiricus, and the commentators on
Aristotle, who may be considered as authorities at
second hand for the teaching of the Stoics; but it is
more than doubtful whether everything which they
mention as Stoic teaching really belongs to the older
members of that School. That teaching can, however, be
ascertained with sufficient certainty on most of the
more important points, partly by comparing accounts
when they vary, partly by looking to definite
statements on which authorities agree for the teaching
and points of difference between individual
philosophers, such as Zeno, Cleanthes, Chrysippus;
partly too by consulting such fragments of their
writings as are still extant. Yet, when the chief
points have been settled in this way, many
difficulties still remain. In the first place, it will
be found that only isolated points of their teaching,
with at most a few arguments on which to base them,
are recorded; but the real connection of their tenets,
and the motives which gave rise to them, can only be
known by conjecture. Had the writings of Zeno and
Chrysippus come down to us in their entirety, we
should have had a much surer foundation on which to
build, and far less would have been left to
conjecture. An opportunity, too, would then have been
afforded of tracing the inward growth of the Stoic
teaching, and of deciding how much of that teaching
was due to Zeno, and how much to Chrysippus. That this
work of discrimination can now only be done very
imperfectly is the second difficulty, and it arises
from the nature of the authorities. It may be
ascertained without difficulty what the teaching of
the Stoics was since the time of Chrysippus, but only
on a few points are the differences between Chrysippus
and his predecessors known. For the most part, the
authorities do not hesitate to attribute to the
founder of the School all that was known to them as
belonging to its later members, just as everything
Pythagorean was directly attributed to Pythagoras, and
everything Platonic to Plato. Still, there can be no
doubt that the Stoic teaching was very considerably
expanded by Chrysippus, and altered in many ways. But
how considerable the alterations were, and in what
they consisted, are questions upon which there is
little direct evidence.
The path is thus marked out, which must be followed in
giving an exposition of the Stoic philosophy. If full
information were forthcoming respecting the rise of
the Stoic system and the form it assumed under each
one of its representatives, it would be most natural
to begin by reviewing the motives which led Zeno to
his peculiar teaching, and by describing the system as
it grew up. Next it would be right to trace step by
step the changes and expansions which it received at
the hands of each succeeding teacher. In default of
the necessary information for such a treatment of the
subject, it will be better to pursue another course.
The Stoic teaching will have to be treated as a whole,
in which the contributions of individuals can no
longer be distinguished. It will have to be set forth
in the form which it assumed after the time of
Chrysippus. The share of individuals in constructing
the system, and their deviations from the general
type, cannot be considered, except in cases where they
are placed beyond doubt by the statements of the
ancients, or by well-founded historical surmises.
Stoicism will have to be described in the first place
as it is traditionally known, without having its
principles explained or resolved into their component
factors; without even considering how they grew out of
previous systems. Not till this has been done will it
be possible to analyze the purport and structure of
the system, so as to fathom its leading motives, to
understand the connection of its various parts, and
thus to ascertain its true position in history.
Proceeding next to ask in what form the problem of
philosophy presented itself to the Stoics, three
points deserve to be specially noticed. (1) In the
first place, philosophy was determined practically by
an end in view. (2) The character of this end was
decided by the idea of conformity with reason; and
(3), this view was substantiated by intellectual
proof.
The real business of all philosophy, according to the
Stoics, is the moral conduct of man. Philosophy is the
exercise of an art, and more particularly of the
highest art--virtue: it is therefore the learning of
virtue. Now virtue can only be learned by exercise,
and therefore philosophy is at the same time virtue,
and the several parts of philosophy are so many
distinct virtues. Morality is the central point
towards which all other inquiries converge. Even
natural science, although lauded as the inmost shrine
of philosophy, is, according to Chrysippus, only
necessary for the philosopher to enable him to
distinguish between things good and evil, between what
should be done and what should be left undone. So far
from approving pure speculation, which Plato and
Aristotle had commended as the height of human
happiness, Chrysippus plainly asserted that to live
for speculation is equivalent to living only for
pleasure. With this view of Chrysippus most of the
statements of the Stoics as to the relation of various
branches of philosophy to each other agree, although
there is a certain amount of vagueness about them,
owing to reasons which will shortly be mentioned; and
on no other hypothesis can the internal structure and
foundation of their system be satisfactorily
explained. It is enough to remark here, as has been
done before, that the most important and most
distinctive points established by the Stoic School
belong to the sphere of ethics. In logic and natural
science the School displays far less independence, for
the most part following older teachers; and it is
expressly noted, as a deviation from the ordinary
teaching of the School, that Herillus, the pupil of
Zeno, declared knowledge to be the highest good, thus
making it the chief end in philosophy.
This view of the problem of philosophy is more
precisely defined by the Stoic doctrine of virtue.
Philosophy should lead to right action and to virtue.
But right action is, according to the Stoics, only
rational action, and rational action is action which
is in harmony with human and inanimate nature. Virtue
consists therefore in bringing man’s actions into
harmony with the laws of the universe, and with the
general order of the world. This is only possible when
man knows that order and those laws; and thus the
Stoics are brought back to the principles of Socrates,
that virtue may be learned; that knowledge is
indispensable for virtue, or rather that virtue is
identical with right knowledge. They define virtue in
so many words as knowledge, vice as ignorance. If
sometimes they seem to identify virtue with strength
of will, it is only because they consider strength of
will to be inseparable from knowledge, so that the one
cannot be conceived without the other. Hence the
practical study of philosophy conducts with them to
the intellectual; philosophy is not only virtue, but
without philosophy no virtue is possible. Granting
that the attainment of virtue, and the happiness of a
moral life, are the chief ends which the Stoics
propose to themselves, still the possession of a
comprehensive scientific knowledge is indispensable,
as the only means thereto.
These remarks prove the need for the Stoics of that
kind of scientific knowledge which has to do with
life, the morals and the actions of mankind, in short,
of Ethics. Whether further scientific knowledge is
necessary, was a question on which the earliest
adherents of the Stoic teaching expressed different
opinions. Zeno’s pupil, Aristo of Chios, held (a) that
the sole business of man is to pursue virtue, and that
the sole use of language is to purify the soul. This
purifying process, however, is neither to be found in
logical subtleties nor in natural science. Logic, as
doing more harm than good, he compared to a spider’s
web, which is as useless as it is curious; or else to
the mud on a road. Those who studied it he likened to
people eating lobsters, who take a great deal of
trouble for the sake of a little bit of meat enveloped
in much shell. Convinced, too, that the wise man is
free from every deceptive infatuation, and that doubt,
for the purpose of refuting which logic has been
invented, can be more easily overcome by a healthy
tone of mind than by argument, he felt no particular
necessity for logic. Nay, more, he considered that
excessive subtlety transforms the healthy action of
philosophy into an unhealthy one. Just as little was
Aristo disposed to favor the so-called encyclical
knowledge: those who devote themselves to this
knowledge instead of to philosophy he compared to the
suitors of Penelope, who won the maids but not the
mistress. Natural science would probably have received
a more favorable treatment at the hands of Aristo, had
he not shared the opinion of Socrates, that it is a
branch of knowledge which transcends the capacity of
the human mind; and having once embraced this notion,
he was inclined to pronounce all physical inquiries
useless. His attitude towards other sciences has
therefore been generally expressed by saying that he
excluded from philosophy both logic and natural
science, on the ground that both are useless; the
former being irrelevant, and the latter transcending
our powers. Even ethics was limited by Aristo to most
fundamental notions--to inquiries into good and evil,
virtue and vice, wisdom and folly. The special
application of these notions to the moral problems
suggested by particular relations in life, he declared
to be useless and futile; proper for nursemaids and
trainers of young children, but not becoming for
philosophers; wherever there is a proper knowledge and
a right disposition, such particular applications will
come of themselves without teaching; but when these
are wanting, all exhortations are useless.
These views are mentioned as peculiar to Aristo, and
as points in which he differed from the rest of his
School; and, to judge from his controversial tone, the
opposite views were those almost universally
entertained by Stoics. That controversial tone, in
fact, appears to have been directed not only against
assailants from without--such as the Peripatetics and
Platonists--but far more against those members of the
Stoic School, who attached greater importance than he
did to special ethical investigations, and to logical
and physical inquiries. Among their number must have
been Zeno and Cleanthes; for Zeno set the example to
his School of dividing philosophy into logic, ethics,
and natural science; witness the titles of his logical
and physical treatises and also the statements in
reference to theoretical knowledge and natural science
which are expressly attributed to him. Moreover, Zeno
himself recommended to others, and himself pursued,
logical inquiries. Indeed, his whole mental habit,
with its keen appreciation of even the subtleties of
the Megarians, bears testimony to an intellectual type
of thought which is far removed from that of Aristo.
It was, moreover, Zeno who chose that curt and
unadorned logical style, which is found in its
greatest perfection in Chrysippus. Logical and
scientific treatises are also known to have been
written by Cleanthes, who, in his division of
philosophy, allotted separate parts to logic, to
rhetoric, and to natural science, and the name of
Cleanthes is one of frequent occurrence, not only in
the natural science, but more particularly in the
theology of the Stoics. Still more exhaustive
inquiries into logic and natural science appear to
have been set on foot by Sphaerus. These prove that
the energies of the Stoic School must have been
directed to these subjects before the time of
Chrysippus, although these branches of science were no
doubt subservient to ethics, whilst ethics held the
most important and highest place in their philosophy.
At a later time, when Chrysippus had expanded the
system of the Stoics in every direction, and especial
attention had been devoted to logic, the necessity for
these sciences came to be generally recognized. More
especially was this the case with regard to natural
science, including ‘theology.’ All ethical inquiries
must start, according to Chrysippus, with considering
the universal order and arrangement of the world. Only
by a study of nature, and a knowledge of what God is,
can anything really satisfactory be stated touching
good and evil, and all that is therewith connected.
Less obvious is the connection between logic and the
ultimate aim of all philosophical inquiries. Logic is
compared by the Stoics to the shell of an egg, or to
the wall of a city or garden; and is considered to be
of importance, because it contributes towards the
discovery of truth and the avoiding of error. The
value of logic in their eyes is, therefore,
essentially due to its scientific method; its proper
aim is the art of technical reasoning; and thus,
following Aristotle, an unusually full treatment is
allowed to the doctrine of the syllogism. That the
value attached to logic must have been considerable is
proved by the extraordinary care which Chrysippus
devoted to the subject; hence, the Stoics would never
allow, in dispute with the Peripatetics, that logic
was only an instrument, and not a part of philosophy.
To later writers that stiff logical mode of
description, regardless of all beauty of language,
appeared to be a peculiarity of the Stoic school, and
hence that School was characteristically known as the
School of the Reasoners. Frequent instances will be
found hereafter of the Stoic preference for dry
argument and formal logic; in Chrysippus this fondness
degenerated to a dry formalism devoid of taste.
The foregoing remarks have already established the
three main divisions of philosophy which were
universally acknowledged by the Stoics--Logic, Natural
Science, and Ethics. As regards the relative worth and
sequence of these divisions, very opposite views may
be deduced from the principles of the Stoic teaching,
there can be no doubt, and, indeed, all are agreed in
allowing, that logic was subservient to the other two
branches of science, being only an outpost of the
system. If therefore in arranging the parts the
advance is from the less important to the more
important, logic will hold the first place. It will
occupy the last place if the opposite mode of
procedure is followed. But the relation existing
between ethics and natural science is an open
question. On the one hand, ethics appears to be the
higher science, the crowning point of the system, the
subject towards which the whole philosophical activity
of the School was directed; for philosophy is
practical knowledge, and its object is to lead to
virtue and happiness. On the other hand, virtue and
the destiny of man consist in conformity to the laws
of nature, which it is the province of science to
investigate. Therefore, natural science has the higher
object. It lays down the universal laws which in
ethics are applied to man. To it, therefore, in the
graduated scale of sciences, belongs the higher rank.
In attempting to harmonize these opposite
considerations, the Stoics did not always succeed. At
one time natural science is preferred to ethics, at
another time ethics to natural science, in the
enumeration of the several branches of philosophy. In
the comparisons by means of which their relations to
each other were explained, ethics appears at one time,
at another time natural science, to be the aim and
soul of the whole system. Different views were even
entertained in reference to the order to be followed
in teaching these sciences. In describing the Stoic
system, preference will be here given to that
arrangement which begins with logic end goes on to
natural science, ending with ethics; not only because
that arrangement has among its supporters the oldest
and most distinguished adherents of the Stoic School,
but also because in this way the internal relation of
the three parts to each other can be most clearly
brought out. Allowing that, in many essential
respects, natural science is modified by ethical
considerations; still, in the development of the
system, the chief results of science are used as
principles on which ethical doctrines are founded; and
logic, although introduced later than the other two
branches of study, is the instrument by means of which
they are put into scientific shape. If the opportunity
were afforded of tracing the rise of the Stoic
teaching in the mind of its founder, it would probably
be possible to show how the physical and logical parts
of the system gradually gathered around the original
kernel of ethics. But knowing Stoicism only as we do
from the form which it attained after the time of
Chrysippus, it will be enough, in analyzing that form,
to proceed from without to within, and to advance from
logic through natural science to ethics. When this has
been done it will be time to go back over the same
ground, and to explain how from the ethical tone of
Stoicism its peculiar speculative tenets may be
deduced.
CHAPTER V. Logic of the Stoics.
UNDER the head of Logic, in the Stoic use of
the term after the time of Chrysippus, a number of
intellectual inquiries are included which would not
now be considered to belong to philosophy at all. One
common element, however, characterized them all--they
all referred to the formal conditions of thought and
expression. Logic was primarily divided into two
parts, sharply marked off from each other, roughly
described as the art of speaking continuously and the
art of conversing. The former is known as Rhetoric,
the latter as Dialectic. To these two was added, as a
third part, the doctrine of a standard of truth, or
the theory of knowledge; and, according to some
authorities, a fourth part, consisting of inquiries
into the formation of conceptions. By others, these
inquiries were regarded as the third main division,
the theory of knowledge being included under
dialectic. By rhetoric, however, little else was meant
than a collection of artificial rules, of no
philosophical value; and dialectic was in great
measure occupied with inquiries referring to precision
of expression. Dialectic is defined to be the science
or art of speaking well; and since speaking well
consists in saying what is becoming and true,
dialectic is used to express the knowledge of what is
true or false, or what is neither one nor the other,
correctness of expression being considered inseparable
from correctness of thought. Words and thoughts are,
according to this view, the very same things regarded
under different aspects. The same idea, which is a
thought as long as it resides within the breast, is a
word as soon as it comes forth. Accordingly, dialectic
consists of two main divisions, treating respectively
of utterance and the thing uttered, thoughts and
words. Both divisions, again, have several
subdivisions, which are only imperfectly known to us.
Under the science of utterance, which was generally
placed before the science of things uttered, are
included, not only instruction as to sounds and
speech, but also the theories of poetry and music,
these arts being ranked under the head of the voice
and of sound on purely external considerations. What
is known of the teaching of the Stoics on these
subjects, consisting, as it does, of a mass of
definitions, differences, and divisions, has so little
philosophical value, that it need not detain attention
longer. Two parts only of the Stoic logic possess any
real interest--the theory of knowledge, and that part
of dialectic which treats of ideas, and which in the
main agrees with our formal logic.
The Stoic theory of knowledge turns about the inquiry
for a criterion or standard by which what is true in
notions may be distinguished from what is false. Since
every kind of knowledge, no matter what be its object,
must be tested by this standard, it follows that the
standard cannot be sought in the subject-matter of
notions, but, on the contrary, in their form. The
inquiry after a standard becomes therefore identical
with another--the inquiry as to what kind of
notions supply a knowledge that may be depended upon,
or what activity of the power of forming conceptions
carries with it a pledge of its own truth. It is
impossible to answer these questions without
investigating the origin, the various kinds, and the
value and importance of notions. Hence the problem
proposed to the Stoics is reduced to seeking by an
analysis of notions to obtain a universally valid
standard by which their truth may be tested.
Whether this inquiry was pursued by the older Stoics
in all its comprehensiveness is a point on which we
have no information. Boethius, whose views on this
subject were attacked by Chrysippus, had assumed the
existence of several standards, such as Reason,
Perception, Desire, Knowledge. Others, in the vaguest
manner, had spoken of Right Reason as being the
standard of truth. Hence it may be inferred that
before the time of Chrysippus the Stoics had no
distinctly developed theory of knowledge. Nevertheless
there are expressions of Zeno and Cleanthes still
extant which prove that the essential parts of the
later theory were already held by these philosophers,
although it is no doubt true that it first received
that scientific form in which alone it is known to us
at the hands of Chrysippus.
The character of this theory of knowledge appears
mainly in three particulars:--(1) In the importance
attached by the Stoics to the impressions of the
senses. This feature they inherited from the Cynics
and shared with the Epicureans. (2) In the exaltation
of expression into a conception--a trait
distinguishing this from either of the two other
contemporary Schools. (3) In the practical turn given
to the question of a criterion or standard of truth.
We proceed to the expansion of this theory in detail.
The origin of all perceptions may be referred to the
action of some object on the soul, the soul at birth
resembling a blank page, and only receiving definite
features by experience from without. By the elder
Stoics, this action of objects on the soul was
regarded as grossly material, Zeno defining a
perception to be an impression made on the
soul, and Cleanthes took this definition so literally
as to compare the impression on the soul to the
impression made by a seal on wax. Being himself a very
exact pupil of Zeno, Cleanthes probably rendered the
views of Zeno correctly in this comparison. The
difficulties of this view were recognized by
Chrysippus, who accordingly defined a perception to be
the change produced in the soul by an object,
or, more accurately, the change produced thereby in
the ruling part of the soul; and whereas his
predecessors had only considered sensible things to be
objects, he included among objects conditions and
activities of the mind. The mode, however, in which
the change was produced in the soul did not further
engage his attention.
It follows, as a necessary corollary from this view,
that the Stoics regarded sensation as the only source
of all perceptions: the soul is a blank leaf,
sensation is the hand which fills it with writings.
But this is not all. Perceptions give rise to memory,
repeated acts of memory to experience, and conclusions
based on experience suggest conceptions which go
beyond the sphere of direct sensation. These
conclusions rest either upon the comparison, or upon
the combination of perceptions, or else upon analogy;
some add, upon transposition and contrast. The
formation of conceptions by means of these agencies
sometimes takes place methodically and artificially,
at other times naturally and spontaneously. In the
latter way are formed the primary conceptions, which
were regarded by the Stoics as the natural types of
truth and virtue, and as the distinctive possession of
rational beings. To judge by many expressions, it
might seem that by primary conceptions, or innate
ideas were meant; but this view would be opposed to
the whole character and connection of the system. In
reality, these primary conceptions are only those
conceptions which, by reason of the nature of thought,
can be equally deduced by all men from experience;
even the highest ideas, those of good and evil, having
no other origin. The artificial formation of
conceptions gives rise to knowledge, which is defined
by the Stoics to be a fixed and immovable conception,
or system of such conceptions. Persistently
maintaining, on the one hand, that knowledge is a
system of artificial conceptions, impossible without a
logical process, they must, on the other hand, have
felt it imperative from this platform that knowledge
should agree in its results with primary conceptions,
agreement with nature being in every department their
watchword. For them it was as natural to derive
support for their system from a supposed agreement
with nature, as it was easy for their opponents to
show that this agreement with nature was imaginary,
and that many of their assertions were wholly opposed
to general opinions.
Perceptions, and the conclusions based upon them,
being thus, according to the Stoics, the two sources
of all notions, the further question arises, How are
these two sources related to each other? It might have
been expected that only perceptions would be stated to
be originally and absolutely true, since all general
conceptions are based on them. Nevertheless, the
Stoics are far from saying so. Absolute certainty of
conviction they allow only to knowledge, and therefore
declare that the truth of the perceptions of the
senses depends on their relation to thought. Truth and
error do not belong to disconnected notions, but to
notions combined in the form of a judgment, and a
judgment is produced by an effort of thought. Hence
sensations, taken alone, are the source of no
knowledge, knowledge first arising when the activity
of the understanding is allied to sensation. Or,
starting from the relation of thought to its object,
since like can only be known by like according to the
well-known adage, the rational element in the
universe can only be known by the rational element in
man. But again, the understanding has no other
material to work upon but that supplied by sensation,
and general conceptions are only obtained from
sensation by conclusions. The mind, therefore, has the
capacity of formally working up the material supplied
by the senses, but to this material it is limited.
Still, it can progress from perceptions to notions not
immediately given in sensation, such as the
conceptions of what is good and of God. And since,
according to the Stoic teaching, material objects only
possess reality, the same vague inconsistency may be
observed in their teaching as has been noticed in
Aristotle--reality attaching to individuals, truth to
general notions. This inconsistency, however, is more
marked in their case than in that of Aristotle,
because the Stoics so far adhere to the Cynic
nominalism as to assert that no reality attaches to
thought. Such an assertion makes it all the more
difficult to understand how greater truth can be
attributed to thought, unreal as it is said to be,
than to sensations of real and material objects. Do we
then ask in what the peculiar character of thought
consists, the Stoics, following Aristotle, reply that
in thought the idea of universality is added to that
which presents itself in sensation as a particular.
More importance was attached by them to another
point--the greater certainty which belongs to thought
than to sensation. All the definitions given above
point to the immovable strength of conviction as the
distinctive feature of knowledge; and of like import
is the language attributed to Zeno, comparing simple
sensation with an extended finger, assent, as being
the first activity of the power of judgment, with a
closed hand, conception with the fist, and knowledge
with one fist firmly grasped by the other. According
to this view, the whole difference between the four
processes is one of degree, and depends on the greater
or less strength of conviction, on the mental exertion
and tension. It is not an absolute difference in kind,
but a relative difference, a gradual shading off of
one into the other.
From these considerations it follows that in the last
resort only a relative distinction is left whereby the
truth of notions may be tested. Even the general
argument for the possibility of knowledge starts with
the Stoics by practically taking something for
granted. Without failing to urge intellectual
objections--and often most pertinent ones--against
Skepticism, as was indeed natural, particularly since
the time of Chrysippus, the Stoics nevertheless
specially took up their stand on one point, which was
this, that, unless the knowledge of truth were
possible, it would be impossible to act on fixed
principles and convictions. Thus, as a last bulwark
against doubt, practical needs are appealed to.
The same result is obtained from a special inquiry
into the nature of the standard of truth. If the
question is asked, How are true perceptions
distinguished from false ones? the immediate reply
given of by the Stoics is, that a true perception is
one which represents a real object as it really is.
You are no further with this answer, and the question
has again to be asked, How may it be known that a
perception faithfully represents a reality? The Stoics
can only reply by pointing to a relative, but not to
an absolute, test--the degree of strength with which
certain perceptions force themselves on our notice. By
itself a perception does not necessarily carry
conviction or assent; for there can be no assent until
the faculty of judgment is directed towards the
perception, either for the purpose of allowing or of
rejecting it, truth and error residing in judgment.
Assent therefore, generally speaking, rests with us,
as does also the power of decision; and a wise man
differs from a fool quite as much by conviction as by
action. Some of our perceptions are, however, of such
a kind that they at once oblige us to bestow on them
assent, compelling us not only to regard them as
probable, but also as true and conformable to the
actual nature of things. Such perceptions produce in
us that strength of conviction which the Stoics call a
conception; they are therefore termed conceptional
perceptions. Whenever a perception forces itself upon
us in this irresistible form, we are no longer dealing
with a fiction of the imagination, but with something
real; but whenever the strength of conviction is
wanting, we cannot be sure of the truth of our
perception. Or, expressing the same idea in the
language of Stoicism, conceptional or irresistible
perceptions, are the standard of truth. The test of
irresistibility was, in the first place, understood to
apply to sensations from without, such sensations,
according to the Stoic view, alone supplying the
material for knowledge. An equal degree of certainty
was, however, attached to terms deduced from
originally true data, either by the universal and
natural exercise of thought, or by scientific
processes of proof. Now, since among these derivative
terms some--the primary conceptions, for
instance--serve as the basis for deriving others, it
may in a certain sense be asserted that sensation and
primary conceptions are both standards of truth. In
strict accuracy, neither sensation nor primary
conceptions can be called standards. The real
standard, whereby the truth of a perception is
ascertained, consists in the power, inherent in
certain perceptions, of carrying conviction--a power
which belongs, in the first place, to sensations,
whether of objects without or within, and, in the next
place, to primary conceptions formed from them in a
natural way. On the other hand, conceptions and terms
formed artificially can only have their truth
established by being subjected to a scientific process
of proof. How, after these statements, the Stoics
could attribute a greater strength of conviction to
artificial than to primary conceptions; how they could
raise doubts as to the trustworthiness of simple
sensations, is one of the paradoxes of the Stoic
system, which prove the existence, as in so many other
systems, of a double current of thought. There is, on
the one hand, a seeking for what is innate and
original, a going back to nature, an aversion to
everything artificial and of human device, inherited
by Stoicism from its ancestral Cynicism. On the other
hand, there is a desire to supplement the Cynic appeal
to nature by a higher culture, and to assign
scientific reasons for truths which the Cynics laid
down as self-evident.
The latter tendency will alone explain the care and
precision which the Stoics devoted to studying the
forms and rules which govern intellectual processes.
Attention to this branch of study may be noticed in
Zeno and his immediate successors at the first
separation of Stoicism from Cynicism. Aristo is the
only Stoic who is opposed to it, his whole habit of
mind being purely that of a Cynic. In Chrysippus it
attained its greatest development, and by Chrysippus
the formal logic of the Stoics reached scientific
completeness. In later times, when Stoicism reverted
more nearly to its original Cynic type, and appealed
directly to the immediate suggestions of the mind, it
lost its interest in logic, as may be observed in
Musonius, Epictetus, and others. For the present,
however, let it suffice to consider the logic of
Chrysippus, as far as that is known to us.
The term formal logic is here used to express those
investigations which the Stoics included under the
doctrine of utterance. The common object of those
inquiries is that which is thought, or, as the Stoics
called it, that which is uttered, understanding
thereby the substance of thought--thought regarded by
itself as a distinct something, differing alike from
the external object to which it refers, from the sound
by which it is expressed, and from the power of mind
which produces it. For this reason, they maintain that
only utterance is not material; things are always
material; even the process of thought consists in a
material change within the soul, and an uttered word,
in a certain movement of the atmosphere. A question is
here suggested in passing, which should not be lost
sight of, viz. How far was it correct for the Stoics
to speak of thoughts as existing, seeing they are not
material, since, according to their teaching, reality
only belongs to material things?
Utterance may be either perfect or imperfect. It is
perfect when it contains a proposition; imperfect when
the proposition is incomplete. The portion of logic,
therefore, which treats of utterance falls into two
parts, devoted respectively to the consideration of
complete and incomplete expression.
In the section devoted to incomplete expression, much
is found which we should include under grammar rather
than under logic. Thus all incomplete expressions are
divided into two groups--one group includes proper
names and adjectives, the other includes verbs. These
two groups are used respectively to express what is
essential and what is accidental, and are again
divided into a number of subdivisions and varieties.
To this part of logic investigations into the
formation and division of conceptions, and the
doctrine of the categories, properly belong; but it
cannot be said with certainty what place they occupy
in the logic of the Stoics.
Certain it is that these researches introduced little
new matter. All that is known of the Stoic views in
reference to the formation, the mutual relation and
the analysis of conceptions, differs only from the
corresponding parts in the teaching of Aristotle by
the change of a few expressions, and a slightly
altered order of treatment.
Of greater importance is the Stoic doctrine of the
categories. In this branch of logic, the Stoics again
follow Aristotle, but not without deviating from him
in three points. Aristotle referred his categories to
no higher conception, but looked upon them severally
as the highest class-conceptions; the Stoics referred
them all to one higher conception. Aristotle
enumerated ten categories; the Stoics thought that
they could do with four, which four only partially
coincide with those of Aristotle. Aristotle placed the
categories side by side, as co-ordinate, so that no
object could come under a second category in the same
respect in which it came under the first one; the
Stoics placed them one under the other, as
subordinate, so that every preceding category is more
accurately determined by the next succeeding one.
The highest conception of all was apparently by the
older Stoics declared to be the conception of Being.
Since, however, speaking strictly, only what is
material can be said to have any being, and many of
our notions refer to incorporeal and therefore unreal
objects, the conception of Something was in later
times put in the place of the conception of Being.
This indefinite Something comprehends alike what is
material and what is not material--in other words,
what has being and what has not being; and the Stoics
appear to have made this contrast the basis of a real
division of things. When it becomes a question,
however, of formal elementary conceptions or
categories, other points are emphasized which have no
connection with the division into things material and
things not material. Of this kind are the four highest
conceptions,--all subordinate to the conception of
Something, viz. subject-matter or substance,
property or form, variety, and variety
of relation.
The first of these categories denotes the
subject-matter of things in themselves, the material
of which they are made, irrespective of any and every
quality, the something which underlies all definite
being, and which alone has a substantial value.
Following Aristotle, the Stoics distinguish, in this
category of matter, between matter in general, or
universal matter, and the particular matter or
material out of which individual things are made. The
former alone is incapable of being increased or
diminished. Far otherwise is the material of which
particular things are made. This can be increased and
diminished, and, indeed, is ever undergoing change; so
much so, that the only feature which continues the
same during the whole term of its existence and its
quality.
The second category, that of property or form,
comprises all those essential attributes, by means of
which a definite character is impressed on matter
otherwise indeterminate. If the definite character be
one which belongs to a group or class, it is called a
common quality--or, if it be something peculiar and
distinctive, it is called a distinctive quality.
Properties therefore combined with matter constitute
the special materials out of which individual things
are made; and quality in this combination corresponds,
as Trendelenburg has well shown, with the form of
Aristotle. It may, in fact, like that, be described as
the active and efficient part of a thing. Aristotle's
form, however, expresses only the non-material side
of a thing, whereas quality is regarded by the Stoics
as something material--in fact, as an air-current.
Hence the mode in which a quality is conceived to
reside in matter is that of an intermingling of
elements. The same theory of intermingling applies of
course to the union of several properties in one and
the same matter, and likewise to the combination of
several attributes to produce a single conception of
quality. In all cases the relation is supposed to be
materialistic, and is explained by the doctrine of the
mutual interpenetration of material things. This
explanation, indeed, could not apply to every kind of
attributes. Unable to dispense entirely with things
not material, the Stoics were obliged to admit the
existence of attributes belonging to immaterial
things, these attributes being, of course, themselves
not material. What idea they formed to themselves of
these incorporeal attributes, when reality was
considered to belong only to things corporeal, it is,
of course, impossible for us to say.
The two remaining categories include everything which
may be excluded from the conception of a thing on the
ground of being either non-essential or accidental.
In as far as such things belong to an object taken by
itself alone, they come under the category of variety;
but when they belong to it, because of its relation to
something else, they come under the category of
variety of relation. Variety includes all accidental
qualities, which can be assigned to any object
independently of its relation to any other object.
Size, color, place, time, action, passion, possession,
motion, state, in short, all the Aristotelian
categories, with the exception of substance, whenever
they apply to an object independently of its relation
to other objects, belong to the category of variety.
On the other hand, those features and states which are
purely relative--such as right and left, sonship and
fatherhood, &c.--come under the category of
variety of relation, and from this category the simple
notion of relation must be distinguished. Simple
relation is not treated as a distinct category, since
it includes not only accidental relations, but also
those essential properties which presuppose a definite
relation to something else--such as knowledge and
perception.
The relation of these four categories to one another
is such, that each preceding category is included in
the one next following, and receives from it a more
definite character. Substance never occurs in reality
without property, but has always some definite quality
to give it a character. On the other hand, property is
never met with alone, but always in connection with
some subject-matter. Variety presupposes some
definite substance, and variety of relation supposes
the existence of variety. It will hereafter be seen
how closely these deductions, and, indeed, the whole
doctrine of the categories, depend on the metaphysical
peculiarities of the Stoic system.
Passing from incomplete to complete utterance, we
come, in the first place, to sentences or
propositions, all the various kinds of which, as they
may be deduced from the different forms of syntax, are
enumerated by the Stoics with the greatest precision.
Detailed information is, however, only forthcoming in
reference to the theory of judgment, which certainly
occupied the chief and most important place in their
speculations. A judgment is a perfect utterance, which
is either true or false. Judgments are divided into
two classes: simple judgments, and composite
judgments. By a simple judgment the Stoics understand
a judgment which is purely categorical. Under the head
of composite judgments are comprised hypothetical,
corroborative, copulative, disjunctive, comparative,
and causal judgments. In the case of simple judgments,
a greater or less definiteness of expression is
substituted in place of the ordinary difference in
respect of quantity; and with regard to quality, they
not only make a distinction between affirmative and
negative judgments, but, following the various forms
of language, they speak of judgments of general
negation, judgments of particular negation, and
judgments of double negation. Only affirmative and
negative judgments have a contradictory relation to
one another; all other judgments stand to each other
in the relation of contraries. Of two propositions
which are related as contradictories, according to the
old rule, one must be true and the other false.
Among composite judgments the most important are the
hypothetical and the disjunctive. As judgments regards
the latter, next to no information has reached us. A
hypothetical judgment is a judgment consisting of two
clauses, connected by the conjunction 'if,' and
related to one another as cause and effect; the former
being called the leading, and the latter the concluding
or inferential clause. In the correctness of
the inference the truth of a hypothetical judgment
consists. As to the conditions upon which the accuracy
of an inference rests, different opinions were
entertained within the Stoic School itself. In as far
as the leading clause states something, from the
existence of which an inference may be drawn for the
statement in the concluding clause, it is also called
an indication or suggestive sign.
The modality of judgments, which engaged the attention
of Aristotle and his immediate pupils so much, was
likewise treated by the Stoics at considerable length;
but of this branch of inquiry so much only is known to
us as concerns possible and necessary judgments, and
it is the outcome chiefly of the contest between
Chrysippus and the Megarian Diodorus. It is in itself
of no great value. By the Stoics, nevertheless, great
value was attached to it, in the hope of escaping
thereby the difficulties which necessarily result from
their views on freedom and necessity.
In their theory of illation, to which the Stoics
attached special value, and on which they greatly
prided themselves, chief attention was paid to
hypothetical and disjunctive inferences. In regard to
these forms of inference, the rules they laid down are
well known: and from these forms they invariably take
their examples, even when treating of inference in
general. According to Alexander, the hypothetical and
disjunctive forms are held to be the only regular
forms of inference; the categorical form is considered
correct in point of fact, but defective in syllogistic
form. In hypothetical inferences a distinction was
also made between such as are connected and such as
are disconnected. In connected inferences the Stoics
look principally at the greater or less accuracy of
expression, and partly at the difference between
correctness of form and truth of matter. They also
remark that true conclusions do not always extend the
field of knowledge; and that those which do frequently
depend on reasons conclusive for the individual, but
not on proofs universally acknowledged. The main
point, however, to be considered in dividing
inferences is their logical form. There are, according
to Chrysippus, who herein adopted the division of
Theophrastus, five original forms of hypothetical
inference, the accuracy of which is beyond dispute,
and to which all other forms of inference may be
referred and by which they may be tested. Yet even
among these five, importance is attached to some in
which the same sentence is repeated tautologically in
the form of a conclusion, which proves how mechanical
and barren must have been the formalism with which the
Stoic logic abounds.
The combination of these five simple forms of
inference gives rise to the composite forms of
inference, all of which may be again resolved into
their simple forms. Among composite forms of
inference, those composed of similar parts are
distinguished from those composed of dissimilar parts;
in the treatment of the former, however, such a
useless formality is displayed, that it is hard to say
what meaning the Stoics attached to them. If two or
more inferences, the conclusion of one of which is the
first premise of the other, are so combined that the
judgment which constitutes the conclusion and premise
at once is omitted in each case, the result is a
Sorites or Chain-inference. The rules prescribed by
the Peripatetics for the Chain-inference are
developed by the Stoics with a minuteness far
transcending all the requirements of science. With
these composite forms of inference Antipater
contrasted other forms having only a single premise,
but it was an addition to the field of logic of very
doubtful worth. On a few other points connected with
the Stoic theory of illation, we have very imperfect
information. The loss, however, is not to be
regretted, seeing that in what we already possess
there is conclusive evidence that the objections
brought against the Stoic logic were really well
deserved, because of the microscopic care expended by
them on the most worthless logical forms.
Next to describing inferences which are valid, another
subject engaged the close attention of the Stoics, and
afforded opportunity for displaying their dialectical
subtlety. This is the enumeration and refutation of
false inferences, and in particular the exposing of
the many fallacies which had become current since the
age of the Sophists and Megarians. In this department,
as might be expected, Chrysippus led the way. Not that
Chrysippus was always able to overcome the
difficulties that arose; witness his remarkable
attitude towards the Chain-inference, from which he
thought to escape by withholding judgment. The
fallacies, however, to which the Stoics devoted their
attention, and the way in which they met them, need
not occupy our attention further.
In all these researches the Stoics were striving to
find firm ground for a scientific process of proof.
Great as was the value which they attached to such a
process, they nevertheless admitted, as Aristotle had
done before, that everything could not be proved. Here
was their weak point. Instead, however, of
strengthening this weak point by means of induction,
and endeavoring to obtain a more complete theory of
induction, they were content with conjectural data,
sometimes self-evident, at other times depending for
their truth on the truth of their inferences. Thus,
their theory of method, like their theory of
knowledge, ended by an ultimate appeal to what is
directly certain.
No very high estimate can therefore be formed of the
formal logic of the Stoics. Incomplete as our
knowledge of that logic may be, still what is known is
enough to determine the judgment absolutely. We see
indeed that the greatest care was expended by the
Stoics since the time of Chrysippus in tracing the
forms of intellectual procedure into their minutest
ramifications, and referring them to fixed types. At
the same time, we see that the real business of logic
was lost sight of in the process, the business of
portraying the operations of thought, and giving its
laws, whilst the most useless trifling with forms was
recklessly indulged in. The Stoics can have made no
discoveries of importance even as to logical forms, or
they would not have been passed over by writers ever
on the alert to note the slightest deviation from the
Aristotelian logic. Hence the whole contribution of
the Stoics to the field of logic consists in their
having clothed the logic of the Peripatetics with a
new terminology, and having developed certain parts of
it with painful minuteness, whilst they wholly
neglected other parts, as was the fate of the part
treating of inference. Assuredly it was no improvement
for Chrysippus to regard the hypothetical rather than
the categorical as the original form of inference.
Making every allowance for the extension of the field
of logic, in scientific precision it lost more than it
gained by the labors of Chrysippus. The history of
philosophy cannot pass over in silence this branch of
the Stoic system, so carefully cultivated by the
Stoics themselves, and so characteristic of their
intellectual attitude. Yet, when all has been said,
the Stoic logic is only an outpost of their system,
and the care which was lavished on it since the time
of Chrysippus indicates the decline of intellectual
originality.
Chapter VI. The Study of Nature. Fundamental
Positions.
OF far more importance in the Stoic system
than the study of logic was the study of nature. This
branch of learning, notwithstanding an appeal to older
views, was treated by them with more independence than
any other. The subjects which it included may be
divided under four heads, viz.: (1) Fundamental
positions; (2) The course, character, and government
of the universe; (3) Irrational nature; and (4) Man.
The present chapter will be devoted to considering the
first of these groups--the fundamental positions held
by the Stoics in regard to nature; among which three
specially deserve notice--their Materialism; their
Dynamical view of the world; and their Pantheism.
Nothing appears more striking to a reader fresh from
the study of Plato or Aristotle than the startling
contrast to those writers presented by the Materialism
of the Stoics. Whilst so far following Plato as to
define a real thing to be anything possessing the
capacity of acting or being acted upon, the Stoics
nevertheless restricted the possession of this power
to material objects. Hence followed their conclusion
that nothing real exists except what is material; or,
if they could not deny existence in some sense or
other to what is incorporeal, they were fain to assert
that essential and real Being only belongs to what is
material, whereas of what is incorporeal only a
certain modified kind of Being can be predicated.
Following out this view, it was natural that they
should regard many things as corporeal which are not
generally considered such; for instance, the soul and
virtue. Nevertheless, it would not be correct to say
that the Stoics gave to the conception of matter or
corporeity a more extended meaning than it usually
bears. For they define a body to be that which has
three dimensions, and they also lay themselves out to
prove how things generally considered to be
incorporeal may be material in the strictest sense of
the term. Thus, besides upholding the corporeal
character of all substances, including the human soul
and God, they likewise assert that properties or forms
are material: all attributes by means of which one
object is distinguished from another are produced by
the existence of certain air-currents, which,
emanating from the center of an object, diffuse
themselves to its extremities, and having reached the
surface, return again to the center to constitute the
inward unity. Nor was the theory of air-currents
confined to bodily attributes. It was applied quite as
much to mental attributes. Virtues and vices are said
to be material, and are deduced from the tension
imparted to the soul by atmospheric substances therein
subsisting. For the same reason the Good is called a
body, for according to the Stoics the Good is only a
virtue, and virtue is a definite condition of that
material which constitutes the soul. In the same sense
also truth is said to the material, personal and not
independent, truth being of course meant, that is to
say, knowledge, or a property of the soul that knows.
And since according to the Stoics knowledge consists
in the presence of certain material elements within
the soul, truth in the sense of knowledge may be
rightly called something material. Even emotions,
impulses, notions and judgments, in so far as they are
due to material causes--the air-currents pouring into
the soul--were regarded as material objects, and for
the same reason not only artistic skill but individual
actions were said to be corporeal. Yet certain
actions, such as walking and dancing, can hardly have
been called bodies by the Stoics, any more than being
wise was called a body; but the objects which produced
these actions, as indeed everything which makes itself
felt, were considered to be corporeal. To us it
appears most natural to refer these actions to the
soul as their originating cause; but the Stoics,
holding the theory of subject-matter and property,
preferred to refer each such action to some special
material as its cause, considering that an action is
due to the presence of this material. The idealism of
Plato was thus reproduced in a new form by the
materialism of the Stoics. Plato had said, a man is
just and musical when he participates in the idea
of justice and music; the Stoics said, a man is
virtuous when the material producing virtue is
in him; musical, when he has the material
producing music.
Moreover, these materials produce the phenomena of
life. Hence, not content with calling them bodies, the
Stoics actually went so far as to call them living
beings. It seems, however, strange to hear such things
as day and night, and parts of the day and parts of
the night, months and years, even days of the month
and seasons of the year, called bodies; but by these
singularly unhappy expressions Chrysippus appears to
have meant little more than that the realities
corresponding to these names depend on certain
material conditions: by summer is meant a certain
state of the air when highly heated by the sun; by
month the moon for a certain definite period during
which it gives light to the earth. From all these
examples one thing is clear, how impossible the Stoics
found it to assign reality to what is not material.
In carrying out this theory, they could not, as might
be expected, wholly succeed. Hence a Stoic could not
deny that there are certain things which it is absurd
to call material. Among such include empty space,
place, time, and expression. Admitting these to be
incorporeal, they still would not allow that they do
not exist at all. This view belongs only to isolated
members of the Stoic School, for which they must be
held personally responsible. How they could harmonize
belief in incorporeal things with their tenet that
existence alone belongs to what is material is not on
record.
The question next before us is: What led the Stoics to
this materialism? It might be supposed that their
peculiar theory of knowledge based on sensation was
the cause; but this theory did not preclude the
possibility of advancing from the sensible to the
super-sensible. It might quite as well be said that
their theory of knowledge was a consequence of their
materialism, and that they referred all knowledge to
sensation, because they could allow no real being to
anything which is not material. The probability
therefore remains that their theory of knowledge and
their materialistic view of nature both indicate one
and the same habit of mind, and that both are due to
the action of the same causes.
Nor will it do to seek for these causes in the
influence exercised by the Peripatetic or
pre-Socratic philosophy on the Stoic School. At first
sight, indeed, it might appear that the Stoics had
borrowed from Heraclitus their materialism, together
with their other views on nature; or else their
materialism might seem to be an expansion of the
metaphysical notions of Plato and Aristotle. For if
Aristotle denied Plato's distinction of form and
matter to such an extent that he would hardly allow
form to exist at all except in union with matter,
might it not appear to others more logical to do away
with the distinction between them in thought, thus
reducing both to a property of matter? Were there not
difficulties in the doctrine of a God external to the
world, of a passionless Reason? Were there not even
difficulties in the antithesis of form and matter,
which Aristotle’s system was powerless to overcome?
And had not Aristoxenus and Dicaearchus before the
time of Zeno, and Strato immediately after his time,
been led from the ground occupied by the Peripatetics
to materialistic views? And yet we must pause before
accepting this explanation. The founder of Stoicism
appears, from what is recorded of his intellectual
growth, to have been repelled by the Peripatetic
School more than by any other; nor is there the least
indication in the records of the Stoic teaching that
that teaching resulted from a criticism of the
Aristotelian and Platonic views of a double origin of
things. Far from it, the proposition that everything
capable of acting or being acted upon must be
material, appears with the Stoics as an independent
axiom needing no further proof.
The supposed connection between the Stoics and
Heraclitus, so far from explaining their materialistic
views, already presumes their existence. Yet long
before Zeno's time the philosophy of Heraclitus as a
living tradition had become extinct. No historical
connection therefore, or relation of original
dependence, can possibly exist between the two, but at
most a subsequent perception of relationship can have
directed Zeno to Heraclitus. Zeno’s own view of the
world was not a consequence, but the cause, of his
sympathy with Heraclitus. In short, neither the
Peripatetics nor Heraclitus can have given the first
impulse to Zeno’s materialism, although they may have
helped in many ways to strengthen his views on that
subject, when already formed.
The real causes for these views must therefore be
sought elsewhere, and will be found in the central
idea of the whole system of the Stoics--the practical
character of their philosophy. Devoting themselves
from the outset with all their energies to practical
inquiries, the Stoics in their theory of nature
occupied the ground of common views, which know of no
real object excepting what is grossly sensible and
corporeal. Their aim in speculation was to discover a
firm basis for human actions. In action, however, men
are brought into direct and experimental contact with
objects. The objects thus presented to the senses we
are brought face to face with in naked reality, nor is
an opportunity afforded for doubting their real being.
Their reality is proved practically, inasmuch as it
affects us and offers itself for the exercise of our
powers. In every such exercise of power, both subject
and object are always material. Even when an
impression is conveyed to the soul of man, the direct
instrument is something material--the voice or the
gesture. In the region of experience there are no such
things as non-material impressions. This was the
ground occupied by the Stoics: a real thing is what
either acts on us, or is acted upon by us. Such a
thing is naturally material; and the Stoics with their
practical ideas not being able to soar above that
which is most obvious, declared that reality belongs
only to the world of bodies.
Herefrom it would appear to follow that only
individual perceptions are true, and that all general
conceptions without exception must be false. If each
notion is incorporeal, and consequently unreal, will
not absence of reality in a much higher degree belong
to the notion of what is general? Individual notions
refer directly to perceptions, i.e. to things
incorporeal; nevertheless they indirectly refer to the
things perceived, i.e. to what is material. But
general notions do not even indirectly refer to
anything corporeal; they are pure fabrications of the
mind, which have nothing real as their object. This
the Stoics explicitly maintained. It was therefore a
gross inconsistency to attribute notwithstanding to
these general conceptions, to which no real objects
correspond, a higher truth and certainty than belongs
to the perceptions of individual objects, but an
inconsistency which the Stoic system made not the
slightest attempt to overcome.
The materialism of the Stoics likewise led to some
remarkable assertions in the province of natural
science. If the attributes of things, the soul and
even the powers of the soul, are all corporeal, the
relation of attributes to their objects, of the soul
to the body, of one body to another body, is that of mutual
intermingling. Moreover, inasmuch as the
essential attributes of any definite material belong
to every part of that material, and the soul resides
in every part of the body, without the soul's being
identical with the body, and without the attributes
being identical with the material to which they
belong, or with one another; it follows that one body
may intermingle with another not only by occupying the
vacant spaces in that body, but by interpenetrating
all its parts, without, however, being fused into a
homogeneous mass with it. This view involves not only
a denial of the impenetrability of matter, but it
further supposes that a smaller body when mingled with
a greater body will extend over the whole of the
latter. It is known as the Stoic theory of universal
intermingling, and is alike different from the
ordinary view of mechanical mixture and from that of
chemical mixture. It differs from the former in that
every part of the one body is interpenetrated by every
part of the other; from the latter, because the bodies
after mixture still retain their own properties. This
peculiar theory, which is one of the much debated but
distinctive features of the Stoic system, cannot have
been deduced from physical causes. On the contrary,
the arguments by which Chrysippus supported it prove
that it was ultimately the result of metaphysical
considerations. We have, moreover, no reason to doubt
it as a fact, inasmuch as the materialistic
undercurrent of the Stoic system affords the best
explanation of it.
Although the stamp of materialism was sharply cut, and
its application fearlessly made by the Stoics, they
were yet far from holding the mechanical theory of
nature, which appears to us to be a necessary
consequence of strict materialism. The universe was
explained on a dynamical theory; the notion of force
was placed above the notion of matter. To matter, they
held, alone belongs real existence; but the
characteristic of real existence they sought in
causation, in the capacity to act and to be acted
upon. This capacity belongs to matter only by virtue
of certain inherent forces, which impart to it
definite attributes. Let pure matter devoid of every
attribute be considered, the matter which underlies
all definite materials, and out of which all things
are made; it will be found to be purely passive, a
something subject to any change, able to assume any
shape and quality, but taken by itself devoid of
quality and unable to produce any change whatsoever.
This inert and powerless matter is first reduced into
shape by means of attributes, all of which suppose
tension in the air-currents which produce them, and
consequently suppose a force producing tension. Even
the shape of bodies, and the place they occupy in
space, is, according to the Stoics, something
derivative, the consequence of tension; tension
keeping the different particles apart in one or the
other particular way. Just as some modern
physiologists construct nature by putting together a
sum of forces of attraction and repulsion, so the
Stoics refer nature to two forces, or, speaking more
accurately, to a double kind of motion--expansion and
condensation. Expansion works outwardly, condensation
inwardly; condensation produces being, or what is
synonymous with it, matter; expansion gives rise to
the attributes of things. Whilst, therefore, they
assert that everything really existing must be
material, they still distinguish in what is material
two component parts--the part which is acted upon, and
the part which acts, or in other words matter
and force.
The Stoics, however, would not agree with Plato and
Aristotle so far as to allow to formal and final
causes a place side by side with this acting force or
efficient cause. If in general anything may be called
a cause which serves to bring about a definite
result--and various kinds of causes may be
distinguished, according as they bring about this
result directly or indirectly, by themselves alone or
by the help of others--in the highest sense there can
be, according to the Stoics, only one acting or
efficient cause. The form is due to the workman, and
is therefore only a part of the efficient cause. The
type-form is only an instrument, which the workman
employs in his work. The final cause or
end-in-chief, in as far as it represents the
workman's intention, is only an occasional cause; in
as far as it belongs to the work he is about, it is
not a cause at all, but a result. There can be but one
pure and unconditional cause, just as there can be but
one matter; and to this efficient cause everything
that exists and everything that takes place must be
referred.
In attempting to form a more accurate notion of this
efficient cause, the first point which deserves
attention is, that the Stoics believed every kind of
action ultimately to proceed from one source. For how
could the world be such a self-circumscribed unity,
such an harmonious whole, unless it were governed by
one and the same force? Again, as everything which
acts is material, the highest efficient cause must
likewise be considered material; and since all
qualities and forces are produced by vapor-like or
fiery elements, can it be otherwise with the highest
acting force? Everywhere warmth is the cause of
nourishment and growth, life and motion; all things
have in themselves their own natural heat, and are
preserved and kept in life by the heat of the sun.
What applies to parts of the world must apply to the
world as a whole; hence heat or fire is the power to
which the life and the existence of the world must be
referred.
This power must be further defined to be the soul of
the world, the highest reason, a kind, beneficent, and
philanthropic being; in short, deity. The universal
belief and the universal worship of God prove this, as
the Stoics think, beyond a doubt; still more accurate
investigation confirms it. Matter can never move or
fashion itself: nothing but a power inherent as the
soul is in man can produce these results. The world
would not be the most perfect and complete thing it is
unless Reason were inherent therein; nor could it
contain any beings possessed of consciousness, unless
it were conscious itself. It could not produce
creatures endowed with a soul and reason, unless it
were itself endowed with a soul and reason. Actions so
far surpassing man’s power could not exist, unless
there were a cause for them in perfection equally
surpassing man. The subordination of means to ends
which governs the world in every part down to the
minutest details would be inexplicable, unless the
world owed its origin to a reasonable creator. The
graduated rank of beings would be incomplete, unless
there were a highest Being of all whose moral and
intellectual perfection cannot be surpassed. Although
this perfection belongs, in the first place, to the
world as a whole, nevertheless, as in everything
consisting of many parts, so in the world the ruling
part must be distinguished from other parts. It is the
part from which all acting forces emanate and diffuse
themselves over the world, whether the seat of this
efficient force be placed in the heaven, as was done
by Zeno, Chrysippus, and the majority of the Stoics;
or in the sun, as by Cleanthes; or in the center of
the world, as by Archedemus. This primary source of
all life and motion, the highest Cause and the highest
Reason, is God. God, therefore, and formless matter,
are the two ultimate grounds of things.
The language used by the Stoics in reference to the
Deity at one time gives greater prominence to the
material, at another to the spiritual side of their
conception of God. As a rule, both are united in
expressions which only cease to be startling when
taken in connection with Stoic views in general. God
is spoken of as being Fire, Ether, Air, most commonly
as being pneuma or Atmospheric-Current,
pervading everything without exception, what is most
base and ugly, as well as what is most beautiful. He
is further described as the Soul, the Mind, or the
Reason of the world; as a united Whole, containing in
Himself the germs of all things; as the Connecting
element in all things; as Universal Law, Nature,
Destiny, Providence; as a perfect, happy, ever kind
and all-knowing Being; nor was it hard to show that
no conception could be formed of God without these
attributes. Both kinds of expression are combined in
the assertion that God is the fiery Reason of the
World, the Mind in Matter, the reasonable
Air-Current, penetrating all things, and assuming
various names according to the material in which He
resides, the artistically molding Fire, containing in
Himself the germs of everything, and producing
according to an unalterable law the world and all that
is therein.
As used in the Stoic system, these expressions
generally mean one and the same thing. It is an
unimportant difference whether the original cause is
described as an Air-Current or as Ether, or as Heat
or as Fire. It is an Air-Current, for Air-Currents
are, as we have already seen, the causes of the
properties of things, giving them shape and
connection. It is also Fire, for by fire is only meant
the warm air, or the fiery fluid, which is sometimes
called Ether, at other times Fire, at other times
Heat, and which is expressly distinguished from
ordinary fire. Moreover the terms, Soul of the world,
Reason of the world, Nature, Universal Law,
Providence, Destiny--all mean the same thing, the one
primary force penetrating the whole world. Even the
more abstract expressions, Law, Providence, Destiny,
have with the Stoics an essentially gross meaning,
implying not only the form according to which the
world is arranged and governed, but also the essential
substance of the world, as a power above everything
particular and individual. If Nature must be
distinguished from Destiny, and both of these notions
again from Zeus, the distinction can only consist
herein, that the three conceptions describe one
original Being at different stages of His
manifestation and growth. Viewed as the whole of the
world it is called Zeus; viewed as the inner power in
the world, Providence or Destiny; and to prove this
identity at the close of every period, so taught
Chrysippus, Zeus goes back into Providence.
Upon closer examination, even the difference between
the materialistic and idealistic description of God
vanishes. God, according to Stoic principles, can only
be invested with reality when He has a material form.
Hence, when He is called the Soul, the Mind, or the
Reason of the world, this language does not exclude,
but rather presupposes, that these conceptions have
bodies; and such bodies the Stoics thought to discern
in that heated fluid which they at one time call the
all-penetrating Breath, at another Ether, or primary
Fire. Each of these two determinations appeared to
them indispensable, and both became identical by
assuming, as the Stoics did, that the infinite
character of the divine Reason depends on the purity
and lightness of the fiery material which composes it.
Seneca is therefore only following out the principles
of his School when he pronounces it indifferent
whether God is regarded as Destiny or as an
all-pervading Breath. Those who charge the Stoics
with inconsistency for calling God at one time Reason,
at another Soul of the universe, at another Destiny,
at another Fire, Ether, or even the Universe, forget
that they are attaching to these terms a meaning
entirely different from that in which they were used
by them.
The more the two sides of the conception of God--the
material and the ideal--are compared, the clearer it
becomes that there is no difference between God and
primary Matter. Both are one and the same substance,
which, when regarded as the universal substratum, is
known as undetermined matter; but when conceived of as
acting force, is called all-pervading Ether,
all-warming Eire, all-penetrating Air, Nature, Soul
of the world, Reason of the world, Providence,
Destiny, God. Matter and power, material and form, are
not, as with Aristotle, things radically different,
though united from all eternity. Far from it, the
forming force resides in matter as such; it is in
itself something material; it is identical with Ether,
or Fire-element, or Breath. Hence the difference
between efficient and material cause, between God and
matter, resolves itself into the difference between
Breath and other elements. This difference, too, is no
original or ultimate difference. According to the
Stoic teaching, every particular element has in
process of time developed out of primary fire or God,
and to God it will return at the end of every period
of the world. It is therefore only a derivative and
passing difference with which we are here concerned.
But taking the conception of Deity in its full
meaning, it may be described as primary matter, as
well as primary power. The sum total of all that is
real is the divine Breath, moving forth from itself
and returning to itself again. Deity itself is primary
fire, containing in itself in germ both God and
matter; the world in its original gaseous condition;
the Universal Substance changing into particular
elements, and from them returning to itself again,
which regarded in its real form as God includes at one
time everything, at another only a part of real
existence.
From what has been said it follows that the Stoics
admitted no essential difference between God and the
world. Their system was therefore strictly
pantheistic. The world is the sum of all real
existence, and all real existence is originally
contained in deity, which is at once the matter of
everything and the creative force which molds this
matter into particular individual substances. We can,
therefore, think of nothing which is not either
immediately deity or a manifestation of deity. In
point of essence, therefore, God and the world are the
same; indeed, the two conceptions are declared by the
Stoics to be absolutely identical. If they have
nevertheless to be distinguished, the distinction is
only derivative and partial. The same universal Being
is called God when it is regarded as a whole, World
when it is regarded as progressive in one of the many
forms assumed in the course of its development. The
difference, therefore, is tantamount to assigning a
difference of meaning to the term world, according as
it is used to express the whole of what exists, or
only the derivative part.
Still this distinction does not depend only upon our
way of looking at things, but it is founded in the
nature of things. Primary force, as such, primary
fire, primary reason, constitute what is primarily
God. Things into which this primary substance has
changed itself are only divine in a derivative sense.
Hence deity, which is ultimately identical with the
whole of the world, may again be described as a part
of the world, as the leading part, as the Soul of the
world, as the all-pervading fiery Breath. The
distinction, however, is only a relative one. What is
not immediately divine is nevertheless divine
derivatively, as being a manifestation of primary
fire; and if the soul of the world is not identical
with the body, at least it pervades every part of that
body. It is a distinction, too, which applies only to
a part of the conditions of the world. At the end of
every period, the sum of all derivative things reverts
to the unity of the divine Being, and the distinction
between what is originally and what is derivatively
divine, in other words, the distinction between God
and the world, ceases.
Boethius alone dissented from the pantheism of the
Stoics by making a real distinction between God and
the world. Agreeing with the other Stoics in
considering deity to be an ethereal Substance, he
would not allow that it resided, as the Soul, within
the whole world, and, consequently, he refused to call
the world a living being. Instead of doing so, he
placed the seat of deity in the highest of the
heavenly spheres, the sphere of the fixed stars, and
made it operate upon the world from this abode. The
opposite view detracted, in his eyes, from the
unchangeable and exalted character of the divine
Being. How anxious he was to vindicate that character
will also be seen in the way in which he differed from
his fellow-Stoics in reference to the destruction of
the world.
Chapter VII. The Study of Nature. Course,
Character, and Government of the Universe.
BY VIRTUE of a law inherent in nature,
Primary Being passes over into particular objects;
for, involving as it does the conception of a forming
and creating force, it must as necessarily develop
into a universe, as a seed or ovum must develop into a
plant or animal. Primary fire--so taught the Stoics,
following Heraclitus--first goes over into vapor, then
into moisture; one part of this moisture is
precipitated in the form of earth, another remains as
water, whilst a third part evaporating constitutes
atmospheric air, and air, again, enkindles fire out of
itself. By the mutual play of these four elements the
world is formed, built round the earth as a center;
heat, as it is developed out of water, molding the
chaotic mass. By the separation of these elements, a
distinction between the active and the passive powers
of nature--between the soul of the world and the body
of the world--becomes apparent. The moisture into
which the primary fire was first changed represents
the body, just as the heat latent in it represents the
soul; or, taking the later fourfold division of the
elements, the two lower ones correspond to matter, the
two higher ones to acting force.
As the distinction between matter and force has its
origin in time, so it will also have an end in time.
Matter which primary Being has separated from itself
to form its body is being gradually resolved into
primary Being again; so that, at the end of the
present course of things, a general conflagration of
the world will restore all things to their original
form, in which everything derivative will have ceased
to exist, and pure Deity, or primary fire, will alone
remain in the original purity. This resolution of the
world into fire or ether, the Stoics thought, would
take place, through the same intermediate stages as
its generation from the primary fire. Cleanthes,
following his peculiar view as to the seat of the
governing force in the world, supposed that its
destruction would come from the sun.
No sooner, however, will everything have returned to
its original unity, and the course of the world have
come to an end, than the formation of a new world will
begin, so exactly corresponding with the previous
world that every particular thing, every particular
person, and every occurrence will recur in it,
precisely as they occurred in the world preceding.
Hence the history of the world and of Deity--as,
indeed, with the eternity of matter and acting force,
must necessarily be the case--revolves in an endless
cycle through exactly the same stages. Still there
were not wanting, even in comparatively early times,
members of the Stoic School who entertained doubts on
this teaching; and among the most distinguished of the
later Stoics some gave it up altogether. Besides the
periodical destruction by fire, periodical
destructions by floods were also assumed; there being,
however, a difference of opinion as to whether the
whole universe, or only the earth and its inhabitants,
were subject to these floods.
One point established by the generation and
destruction of the world--the uncertainty of all
particular things, and the unconditional dependence of
everything on a universal law and the course of the
universe--is a leading one in the Stoic inquiries into
nature. All things in nature come about by virtue of a
natural and unchangeable connection of cause and
effect, as the nature of the universe and the general
law require. This absolute necessity, regulating all
Being and Becoming, is expressed in the conception of
Fate or Destiny. Viewed from the point of view of
natural science, Destiny is only another name for
primary Being, for the all-pervading, all-producing
Breath, for the artistic fire which is the soul of the
world. But again the activity of this Being being
always rational and according to law, Destiny may also
be described as the Reason of the World, as universal
Law, as the rational form of the world's course. When
regarded as the groundwork of natural formations, this
primary Being or general Law is called Nature; but
when it appears as the cause of the orderly
arrangement and development of the world, it is known
as Providence; or in popular language it is called
Zeus, or the will of Zeus; and in this sense it is
said that nothing happens without the will of Zeus.
In action as the creative force in nature, this
universal Reason also bears the name of Generative
Reason. It bears this name more immediately in
relation to the universe, not only as being the
generating power by which all things are produced from
primary fire as from seed according to an inner law,
but because in the present condition of things all
form and shape, all life and reason, grow out of it,
in short, because primary fire and reason contain in
themselves the germ of all things. In the same sense,
generative powers in the plural are spoken of as
belonging to Deity and Nature; and in treating of man,
denote the generative powers as a part of the soul,
and must be thought of as bearing the same relation to
the individual soul that the generative powers of
Nature do to the soul of nature. By the term
Generative Reason, therefore, must be understood the
creative and forming forces in nature, which have
collectively produced the universe, and particular
exercises of which produce individual things. These
forces, agreeably with the ordinary Stoic
speculations, are spoken of as the original material,
or material germ of things. On the other hand, they
also constitute the form of things--the law
which determines their shape and qualities, the
logos--only we must beware of trying to think of form
apart from matter. Just as the igneous or ethereal
material of primary Being is in itself the same as the
forming and creating element in things, the Reason of
the world or the Soul of nature; so the atmospheric
substance in the seeds of individual things, in which
the Stoics thought the generative power alone resides,
is in itself the germ out of which the corresponding
thing is produced by virtue of an inherent law. The
inward form is the only permanent element in things
amid the perpetual change of materials. It constitutes
the identity of the universe; and whereas matter is
constantly changing from one form to another, the
universal law of the process alone continues
unchangeably the same.
All parts of the Stoic system lead so unmistakably to
the conclusion, not only that the world as a whole is
governed by Providence, but that every part of it is
subject to the same unchangeable laws, that no
definite arguments would appear necessary to establish
this point. Nevertheless, the Stoics lost no
opportunity of meeting objections to their views in
the fullest manner. In the true spirit of a Stoic,
Chrysippus appealed to the general conviction of
mankind, as expressed in the names used to denote fate
and destiny, and to the language of poetry. Nor was it
difficult to show that a divine government of the
world followed of necessity from the Stoic conception
of the perfection of God. Besides, in proving the
existence of a God by the argument drawn from the
adaptation of means to ends, a providential government
of the world was at the same time proved. Chrysippus
also thought to defend his theory of necessity in the
same strictly logical manner. For must not every
judgment be either true or false? And does not this
apply to judgments which refer to future events, as
well as to others? Judgments, however, referring to
the future can only be true when what they affirm must
come to pass of necessity; they can only be false when
what they affirm is impossible; and, accordingly,
everything that takes place must follow of necessity
from the causes which produce it.
The same process of reasoning, transferred from the
outer world to the inner world of mind, underlies the
argument from the foreknowledge of God. If in the one
case it is alleged that whatever is true, before it
comes to pass, is necessary, so in the other it is
said to be necessary, if it can be truly known before
it comes to pass.
To this argument may be added a further one to which
the Stoics attached great importance--the argument
from the existence of divination. If it is impossible
to know beforehand with certainty what is accidental,
it is also impossible to predict it.
But the real kernel of the Stoic fatalism is expressed
in the maxim, that nothing can take place without a
sufficient cause, nor, under given circumstances, can
happen differently from what has happened. This were
as impossible, according to the Stoics, as for
something to come out of nothing; were it possible,
the unity of the world would be at an end, consisting,
as it does, in the chain-like dependence of cause
upon cause, and in the absolute necessity of
everything and of every change. The Stoic doctrine of
necessity was the direct consequence of the Stoic
pantheism. The divine power which rules the world
could not be the absolute uniting cause of all things,
if there existed anything in any sense independent of
it, and unless one unchanging causal connection
governed every thing.
Divine Providence, therefore, does not extend to
individual things taken by themselves, but only to
things in their relation to the whole. Everything
being in every respect determined by this relation,
and being consequently subject to the general order of
the world, it follows that we may say that God cares
not only for the universe, but for all individual
members of the universe. The converse of this may also
be asserted with equal justice, viz. that God’s care
is directed to the whole, and not to individuals, and
that it extends to things great, but not to things
small. Directly it always extends to the whole,
indirectly to individuals throughout the whole, in so
far as they are therein contained, and their condition
is determined by its condition. The Stoic notion of
Providence is therefore entirely based on a view of
the universe as a whole; individual things and persons
can only come into consideration as dependent parts of
this whole.
The Stoics were thus involved in a difficulty which
besets every theory of necessity--the difficulty of
doing justice to the claims of morality, and of
vindicating the existence of moral responsibility.
This difficulty became for them all the more pressing
the higher those claims were advanced, and the more
severely they judged the great majority of their
fellow-men. To overcome it, Chrysippus appears to
have made most energetic efforts. The existence of
chance he could not allow, it being his aim to
establish that what seems to be accidental has always
some hidden cause. Nor would he allow that everything
is necessary, since that can only be called necessary
which depends on no external conditions, and is
therefore always true; in other words, what is eternal
and unchangeable, not that which comes to pass in
time, however inevitable it may be. And, by a similar
process of reasoning, he still tried to rescue the
idea of the Possible, little as that idea accords with
the Stoic system.
In reference to human actions, the Stoics did not
allow the freedom of the will, in the proper sense of
the term; but were of opinion that absence of freedom
does not prejudice the character of the will as a
deciding power. For is not one and the same
all-determining power everywhere active, working in
each particular being according to the law of its
nature, in one way in organic beings, in another in
inorganic beings, differently again in animals and
plants, in rational and irrational creatures? And
albeit every action may be brought about by the
co-operation of causes depending on the nature of
things and the character of the agent, is it not still
free, the resultant of our own impulses and decision?
Involuntary it would only be were it produced by
external causes alone, without any co-operation, on
the part of our wills, with external causes. Moral
responsibility, according to the Stoics, depends only
on freedom of the will. What emanates from my will is
my action, no matter whether it be possible for me to
act differently or not. Praise and blame, rewards and
punishment, express the judgment of society relative
to the character of certain persons or actions.
Whether they could have been different, or not, is
irrelevant. Otherwise virtue and vice must be set down
as things not in our power, for which, consequently,
we are not responsible, seeing that when a man is once
virtuous or vicious, he cannot be otherwise; and the
highest perfection, that of the Gods, is absolutely
unchangeable. Chrysippus even endeavored to show, not
only that his whole theory of destiny was in harmony
with the claims of morality and moral responsibility,
but that it presupposed their existence. The
arrangement of the universe, he argued, involves law,
and law involves the distinction between what is
conventionally right and what is conventionally wrong,
between what deserves praise and what deserves blame.
Moreover, it is impossible to think of destiny without
thinking of the world, or to think of the world
without thinking of the Gods, who are supremely good.
Hence the idea of destiny involves also that of
goodness, which again includes the contrast between
virtue and vice, between what is praiseworthy and what
is blameworthy. If his opponents objected that, if
everything is determined by destiny, individual action
is superfluous, since what has been once foreordained
must happen, come what may, Chrysippus replied:--There
is a distinction to be made between simple and complex
predestination; the consequences of human actions
being simply results of those actions, are quite as
much foreordained as the actions themselves.
From these observations, it appears that the Stoics
never intended to allow man to hold a different
position, in regard to destiny, from that held by
other beings. All the actions of man--in fact, his
destiny--are decided by his relation to things: one
individual only differs from another in that one acts
on his own impulse, and agreeably with his own
feelings, whereas another, under compulsion and
against his will, conforms to the eternal law of the
world.
Everything in the world being produced by one and the
same divine power, the world, as regards its
structure, is an organic whole, in respect of its
constitution perfect. The unity of the world, a
doctrine distinguishing the Stoics from the
Epicureans, followed as a corollary from the unity of
primary substance and of primary force. It was further
proved by the intimate connection, or, as the Stoics
called it, the sympathy of all its parts, and, in
particular, by the coincidence of the phenomena of
earth and heaven. The perfection of the world follows
generally from a consideration of fundamental
principles. But the Stoics made use of many arguments
in support of its perfection, appealing, after the
example of preceding philosophers, sometimes to its
beauty, and, at other times, to the adaptation of
means to ends. An appeal to beauty is the assertion of
Chrysippus, that nature made many creatures for the
sake of beauty, the peacock, for instance, for the
sake of its tail;--and the dictum of Marcus Aurelius,
that what is purely subsidiary and subservient to no
purpose, even what is ugly or frightful in nature, has
peculiar attractions of its own; and the same kind of
consideration may have led to the Stoic assertion,
that no two things in nature are altogether alike.
Their chief argument, however, for the beauty of the
world, was based on the shape, the size, and the color
of the heavenly structure.
The other line of argument is followed not so much in
individual expressions. But owing no doubt to the
pre-eminently practical character of its treatment of
things, the Stoic view of nature, like the Socratic,
has ever an eye on the adaptation of means to ends in
the world. As, on the one hand, this adaptation of
means to ends is the most convincing proof of the
existence of deity, so, on the other hand, by it, more
than by anything else, the divine government of the
world makes itself manifest. Like Socrates, however,
they took a very superficial view of the adaptation of
means to ends, arguing that everything in the world
was created for the benefit of some other
thing--plants for the support of animals, animals for
the support and the service of man, the world for the
benefit of Gods and men--not unfrequently degenerating
into the ridiculous and pedantic, in their endeavors
to trace the special end for which each thing exists.
But, in asking the farther question, For what purpose
do Gods and men exist? they could not help being at
length carried beyond the idea of a relative end to
the idea of an end-in-itself. The end for which Gods
and men exist is that of mutual society. Or,
expressing the same idea in language more
philosophical, the end of man is the contemplation and
imitation of the world; man has only importance as
being a part of a whole; only this whole is perfect
and an end-in-itself.
The greater the importance attached by the Stoics to
the perfection of the world, the less were they able
to avoid the difficult problem of reconciling the
various forms of evil in the world. By the attention
which, following the example of Plato, they gave to
this question, they may be said to be the real
creators of the moral theory of the world. The
character of this moral theory was already determined
by their system. Subordinating individuals, as that
system did, to the law of the whole, it met the
charges preferred against the evil found in the world
by the general maxim, that imperfection in details is
necessary for the perfection of the whole. This maxim,
however, might be explained in several ways, according
to the meaning assigned to the term necessary. If
necessity is taken to be physical, the existence of
evil is excused as being a natural necessity, from
which not even deity could grant exemption. If, on the
other hand, the necessity is not a physical one, but
one arising from the relation of means to ends, evil
is justified as a condition or necessary means for
bringing about good. Both views are combined in the
three chief questions involved in the moral theory of
the world: the existence of physical evil, the
existence of moral evil, and the relation of outward
circumstances to morality.
The existence of physical evil gave the Stoics little
trouble, since they refused to regard it as an evil at
all, as will be seen in treating of their ethical
system. It was enough for them to refer evils of this
kind--diseases, for instance---to natural causes, and
to regard them as the inevitable consequences of
causes framed by nature to serve a definite purpose.
Still, they did not fail to point out that many things
only become evil by a perverted use, and that other
things, ordinarily regarded as evils, are of the
greatest value.
Greater difficulty was found by the Stoics to beset
the attempt to justify the existence of moral evil,
and the difficulty was enhanced in their case by the
prevalence and intensity of moral evil in the world
according to their view. By their theory of necessity
they were prevented from shifting the responsibility
for moral evil from natural law or deity on to man,
which is one way out of the difficulty. In not
altogether eschewing this course, and yet refusing to
allow to deity any participation in evil, and
referring evil to the free will and intention of man,
they acted as other systems of necessity have done
before, reserving the final word. The real solution
which they gave to the difficulty is to be found
partly in the assertion that even the deity is not
able to keep human nature free from faults, and partly
in the consideration that the existence of evil is
necessary, as a counterpart and supplement to good,
and that, in the long run, evil will be turned by the
deity into good.
The third point in their moral theory of the world,
the connection between moral worth and happiness,
engaged all the subtlety of Chrysippus and his
followers. To deny any connection between them would
have been to contradict the ordinary views of the
relation of means to ends. Besides, they were prepared
to regard some part of the evils of life as divine
judgments. Still there were facts which could not be
reconciled with this view--the misfortunes of the
virtuous, the good fortune of the vicious--and these
required explanation. The task of explaining them
appears to have involved the Stoics in considerable
embarrassment, nor were their answers altogether
satisfactory. The spirit of their system, however,
rendered only one explanation possible: no real evil
could happen to the virtuous, no real good fortune
could fall to the lot of the vicious. Apparent
misfortune will be regarded by the wise man partly as
a natural consequence, partly as a wholesome training
for his moral powers; there is nothing which is not
matter for rational action: everything that happens,
when rightly considered, contributes to our good;
nothing that is secured by moral depravity is in
itself desirable. With this view it was possible to
connect a belief in divine punishment, by saying that
what to a good man is a training of his powers, is a
real misfortune and consequently a punishment to a bad
man; but we are not in a position to say whether the
scattered hints of Chrysippus really bear this
meaning.
The whole investigation is one involving much doubt
and inconsistency. Natural considerations frequently
intertwine with considerations based on the adaptation
of means to ends; the divine power is oftentimes
treated as a will working towards a definite purpose,
at one time arranging all things for the best with
unlimited power, at another time according to an
unchangeable law of nature; but all these
inconsistencies and defects belong to other moral
theories of the world, quite as much as they belong to
that of the Stoics.
Chapter VIII. Irrational Nature. The Elements. The
Universe.
TURNING from the questions which have
hitherto engaged our attention to natural science in
the stricter sense of the term, we must first touch
upon a few characteristic questions affecting the
general conditions of all existence. In these the
Stoics hold little that is of a distinctive character.
The matter or substance of which all things are made
is corporeal. All that is corporeal is infinitely
divisible, although it is never infinitely divided. At
the same time, all things are exposed to the action of
change, since one material is constantly going over
into another. Herein the Stoics follow Aristotle, in
contrast to the mechanical theory of nature, and
distinguish change in quality from mere motion in
space. They enumerate several varieties of each kind.
Nevertheless, they look upon motion in space as the
primary form of motion. Under the conception of
motion, they, moreover, include action and suffering.
The condition of all action is contact; and since the
motions of different objects in nature are due to
various causes, and have a variety of characters, the
various kinds of action must be distinguished which
correspond with them. In all these statements there is
hardly a perceptible deviation from Aristotle.
Of a more peculiar character are the views of the
Stoics as to the intermingling of substances, to which
reference has already been made. With regard to Time
and Space, they found some innovations on Aristotle’s
theory to be necessary. Space, according to their
view, is the room occupied by a body, the distance
enclosed within the limits of a body. From Space they
distinguish the Empty. The Empty is not met with in
the universe, but beyond the universe it extends
indefinitely. And hence they assert that Space is
limited, like the world of matter, and that the Empty
is unlimited. Nay, not only Space, but Time also, is
by them set down as immaterial; and yet to the
conception of Time a meaning as concrete as possible
is given, in order that Time may have a real value.
Zeno defined Time as the extension of motion;
Chrysippus defines it, more definitely, as the
extension of the motion of the world. The Stoics
affirm the infinite divisibility of Time and Space,
but do not appear to have instituted any deep
researches into this point.
In expanding their views on the origin of the world,
the Stoics begin with the doctrine of the four
elements, a doctrine which, since the time of
Aristotle and Plato, was the one universally accepted.
They even refer this doctrine to Heraclitus, desiring,
above all things, to follow his teaching in natural
science. On a previous occasion, the order and the
stages have been pointed out, according to which
primary fire developed into the several elements in
the formation of the world. In the same order, these
elements now go over one into the other. Yet, in this
constant transformation of materials, in the perpetual
change of form to which primary matter is subject, in
this flux of all its parts, the unity of the whole
still remains untouched. The distinctive
characteristic of fire is heat; that of air is cold;
that of water, moisture; dryness that of the earth.
These essential qualities, however, are not always
found in the elements to which they belong in a pure
state, and hence every element has several forms and
varieties. Among the four essential qualities of the
elements, Aristotle had already singled out two, viz.
heat and cold, as the active ones, calling dryness and
moisture the passive ones. The Stoics do the same,
only more avowedly. They consider the two elements to
which these qualities properly belong to be the seat
of all active force, and distinguish them from the
other two elements, as the soul is distinguished from
the body. In their materialistic system, the finer
materials, as opposed to the coarser, occupy the place
of incorporeal forces.
The relative density of the elements also determines
their place in the universe. Fire and air are light;
water and earth are heavy. Fire and air move away from
the center of the universe; water and earth are drawn
towards it; and thus, from above to below--or, what is
the same thing, from without to within--the four
layers of fire, air, water, and earth are formed. The
fire on the circumference goes by the name of Ether.
Its most remote portion was called by Zeno Heaven; and
it differs from earthly fire not only by its greater
purity, but also because the motion of earthly fire is
in a straight line, whereas the motion of the Ether is
circular. Because of this difference of motion,
Aristotle supposed a radical difference to exist
between these two kinds of fire, but the Stoics did
not feel it necessary to admit such a difference. They
could always maintain that, when beyond the limits of
its proper locality, fire tried to return to it as
quickly as possible, whereas within those limits it
moved in the form of a circle.
Holding this view of the elements, the Stoics, it will
be seen, did not deviate to any very great extent, in
their ideas of the World, from Aristotle and the views
which were generally entertained. In the center of the
Universe reposes the globe of the earth; around it is
water, above the water is air. These three strata form
the kernel of the world, which is in a state of
repose, and around these the Ether revolves in a
circle, together with the stars which are set therein.
At the top, in one stratum, are all the fixed stars;
under the stratum containing the fixed stars are the
planets, in seven different strata--Saturn, Jupiter,
Mars, Mercury, Venus, then the Sun, and in the lowest
stratum, bordering on the region of air, is the Moon.
Thus the world consists, as with Aristotle, of a globe
containing many strata, one above another. That it
cannot be unlimited, as Democritus and Epicurus
maintain, follows from the very nature of body. The
space within the world is fully occupied by the
material of the world, without a vacant space being
anywhere left. Outside the world, however, is empty
space, or else how--the Stoics asked--would there be a
place into which the world could be resolved at the
general conflagration? Moreover, this empty space must
be unlimited; for how can there be a limit, or any
kind of boundary, to that which is immaterial and
non-existent? But although the world is in empty
space, it does not move, for the half of its component
elements being heavy, and the other half light, as a
whole it is neither heavy nor light.
The stars are spherical masses, consisting of fire;
but the fire is not in all cases equally pure, and is
sustained, as Heraclitus taught, by evaporations from
the earth and from water. With this process of
sustentation the motion of the stars is brought into
connection, their orbit extending over the space in
which they obtain their nutriment. Not only the sun,
but the moon also, was believed to be larger than the
earth. Plato and Aristotle had already held that the
stars are living rational divine beings; and the same
view was entertained by the Stoics, not only because
of the wonderful regularity of their motion and
orbits, but also from the very nature of the material
of which they consist. The earth, likewise, is filled
by an animating soul; or else how could it supply
plants with animation, and afford nutriment to the
stars? Upon the oneness of the soul, which permeates
all its parts, depends, in the opinion of the Stoics,
the oneness of the universe.
Most thoroughly, however, did the Stoics--and in
particular, Posidonius--devote themselves to
investigating those problems, which may be summed up
under the name of meteorology. This portion, however,
of their inquiries is of little value for illustrating
their philosophical tenets, and it may suffice to
mention in a note the objects which it included, and
the sources whence information may be obtained. The
same treatment may be given to the few maxims laid
down by the Stoics on the subject of inorganic nature
which have come down to us. Nor need we mention here
the somewhat copious writings of Posidonius, on the
subjects of geography, history, and mathematics.
Little attention was devoted by the Stoics to the
world of plants and animals. About this fact there can
be no doubt, since we neither hear of any treatises by
the Stoics on this subject, nor do they appear to have
advanced any peculiar views. The most prominent point
is, that they divided all things in nature into four
classes--those of inorganic beings, plants, animals,
and rational beings. In beings belonging to the first
class a simple quality constitutes the bond of union;
in those of the second class, a forming power; in
those of the third class, a soul; and in those of the
fourth class, a rational soul. By means of this
division, the various branches of a science of nature
were mapped out, based on a gradually increasing
development of the powers of life. No serious attempt
was made by the Stoics to work out this thought. With
the single exception of man, we know exceedingly
little of their views on organic beings.
Chapter IX. The Study of Nature. Man.
THE Stoic teaching becomes peculiarly
interesting, when it treats of Man; and the line it
here follows is decided by the tone of the whole
system. On the one hand, the Stoic materialism shows
itself most unmistakably in the department of
anthropology; on the other hand, the conviction that
all actions must be referred to active powers, and all
the several active powers to one original power, can
not be held without leading to a belief in the oneness
and in the regulating capacity of the soul. Not only
does it follow, as a corollary from the materialistic
view of the world, that the soul must be in its nature
corporeal, but the Stoics took pains to uphold this
view by special arguments. Whatever, they said,
influences the body, and is by it influenced in turn,
whatever is united with the body and again separated
from it, must be corporeal. How, then, can the soul be
other than corporeal? Whatever has extension in three
dimensions is corporeal; this is the case with the
soul, since it extends in three directions over the
whole body. Thought, moreover, and motion are due to
animal life. Animal life is nurtured and kept in
health by the breath of life. Experience proves that
mental qualities are propagated by natural generation;
they must, therefore, be connected with a corporeal
substratum. As, therefore, the mind is nothing but
fiery breath, so the human soul, is described by the
Stoics sometimes, as fire, sometimes as breath, at
other times, more accurately, as warm breath, diffused
throughout the body, and forming a bond of union for
the body, in the very same way that the soul of the
world is diffused throughout the world, and forms a
bond of union for the world. This warm breath was
believed to be connected with the blood; and hence the
soul was said to be fed by vapors from the blood, just
as the stars are fed by vapors from the earth.
The same hypothesis was also used to explain the
origin of the soul. One part of the soul was believed
to be transmitted to the young in the seed. From the
part so transmitted there arises, by development
within the womb, first the soul of a plant; and this
becomes the soul of a living creature after birth by
the action of the outer air. This view led to the
further hypothesis that the seat of the soul must be
in the breast, not in the brain; since not only breath
and warm blood, but also the voice, the immediate
expression of thought, comes from the breast.
Nor is this hypothesis out of harmony with the notions
otherwise entertained by the Stoics as to the nature
of man. Plato and Aristotle had already fixed on the
heart as the central organ of the lower powers; the
brain they assigned to reason, with the view of
distinguishing the rational from the mere animal soul.
When, therefore, the Stoics assimilated man’s rational
activity to the activity of the senses, deducing both
from one and the same source, it was natural that they
would depart from Aristotle’s view. Accordingly, the
various parts of the soul were supposed to discharge
themselves from their center in the heart into the
several organs, in the form of atmospheric currents.
Seven such parts are enumerated, besides the dominant
part or reason. These seven parts consist of the five
senses, the power of reproduction, and the power of
speech; and, following out their view of the close
relation of speech and thought, great importance is
attached to the power of speech. At the same time, the
Stoics upheld the oneness of the substance of the soul
with greater vigor than either Plato or Aristotle had
done. Reason is with them the primary power, of which
all other powers are only parts, or derivative powers.
Even feeling and desire they derive from it, in direct
contradiction to the teaching of Plato and Aristotle;
and this power is declared to be the seat of personal
identity, a point on which former philosophers had
refrained from expressing any opinion.
The individual soul bears the same relation to the
soul of the universe that a part does to the whole.
The human soul is not only a part, as are all other
living powers, of the universal power of life, but,
because it possesses reason, it has a special
relationship to the Divine Being--a relationship which
becomes closer in proportion as we allow greater play
to the divine element in ourselves, i.e. to reason. On
this very account, however, the soul cannot escape the
law of the Divine Being, in the shape of general
necessity, or destiny. It is a mere delusion to
suppose that the soul possesses a freedom independent
of the world’s course. The human will, like everything
else in the world, is bound into the indissoluble
chain of natural causes, and that irrespectively of
our knowing by what causes the will is decided or not.
Its freedom consists in this, that, instead of being
ruled from without, it obeys the call of its own
nature, external circumstances concurring. To this
power of self-determination, however, the greatest
value is attached. Not only are our actions due to it
to such an extent that only because of it can they be
considered ours, but even our judgments are, as the
Stoics thought, dependent on it. The soul itself being
open to truth or error, convictions are quite as much
in our power as actions: both are alike the necessary
result of the will. And just as the individual soul
does not possess activity independently of the
universal soul, no more can the individual soul escape
the law of destiny. It, too, at the end of the world’s
course, will be resolved into the primary substance,
the Divine Being. The only point about which the
Stoics were undecided was, whether all souls would
last until that time as separate souls, which was the
view of Cleanthes, or only the souls of the wise, as
Chrysippus held.
The effects of the Stoic principles appear
unmistakably in the above statements. They, however,
pervade the whole body of the Stoical views on man.
From one point of view, the theory of necessity, and
the denial of everlasting life after death, seem quite
unintelligible in a system the moral tone of which is
so high; yet the connection of these theories with the
Stoic ethics is very intimate. These theories
commended themselves to the Stoics, as they have done
in later times to Spinoza and Schleiermacher, because
they corresponded with their fundamental view of
morality, according to which the individual is the
instrument of reason in general, and a dependent
portion of the collective universe. Moreover, since
the Stoics admitted a future existence, of limited,
but yet indefinite, length, the same practical results
followed from their belief as from the current belief
in immortality. The statements of Seneca, that this
life is a prelude to a better; that the body is a
lodging-house, from which the soul will return to its
own home; his joy in looking forward to the day which
will rend the bonds of the body asunder, which he, in
common with the early Christians, calls the birthday
of eternal life; his description of the peace of the
eternity there awaiting us, of the freedom and bliss
of the heavenly life, of the light of knowledge which
will there be shed on all the secrets of nature; his
language on the future recognition and happy society
of souls made perfect; his seeing in death a great day
of judgment, when sentence will be pronounced on every
one; his making the thought of a future life the great
stimulus to moral conduct here; even the way in which
he consoles himself for the destruction of the soul by
the thought that it will live again in another form
hereafter--all contain nothing at variance with the
Stoic teaching, however near they may approach to
Platonic or even Christian modes of thought. Seneca
merely expanded the teaching of his School in one
particular direction, in which it approaches most
closely to Platonism; and, of all the Stoics, Seneca
was the most distinctly Platonic.
Excepting the two points which have been discussed at
an earlier time, and one other point relating to the
origin of ideas and emotions, which will be considered
subsequently, little is on record relating to the
psychological views of the Stoics.
Chapter X. Ethics. The General Principles of the
Stoic Ethics. Abstract Theory of Morality.
WHATEVER, attention, the Stoics paid to the
study of nature and to logic, the real kernel of their
system lies, as has been already observed, in their
Ethics; even natural science, that 'most divine part
of philosophy,' was only pursued as an intellectual
preparation for Ethics. In the field of Ethics the
true spirit of the Stoic system may therefore be
expected to appear, and it may be anticipated that
this subject will be treated by them with special
care. Nor is this expectation a vain one; for here the
springs of information flowing freely give ample data
respecting the Stoic doctrine of morality.
Nevertheless, respecting the formal grouping of these
data only vague and contradictory statements are
forthcoming. Moreover, the Stoics appear to have
followed such different courses and to have been so
little afraid of repetition, that it is hardly
possible to obtain a complete survey of their whole
system by following any one of the traditional
divisions.
Proceeding to group the materials in such a way as to
give the clearest insight into the peculiarities and
connection of the Stoic principles, the first
distinction to be made will be one between morality in
general and particular points in morality. In
considering morality in general, those statements
which give the abstract theory of morals will be
distinguished from those which modify it with a view
to meet practical wants. The former again may be
grouped round three points:--the inquiry into the
highest good, that into the nature of virtue, and that
relating to the wise man.
The inquiry into the destiny and end of man turns,
with the Stoics, as it did with all moral philosophers
since the time of Socrates, about the fundamental
conception of the good, and the ingredients necessary
to make up the highest good or happiness. Happiness,
they consider, can only be sought in rational activity
or virtue. Speaking more explicitly, the primary
impulse of every being is towards self-preservation
and self-gratification. It follows that every being
pursues those things which are most suited to its
nature, and that such things only have for it a value.
Hence the highest good--the end-in-chief, or
happiness--can only be found in what is conformable to
nature. Nothing can be conformable to nature for any
individual thing, unless it be in harmony with the law
of the universe, or with the universal reason of the
world; nor, in the case of a conscious and reasonable
being, unless it proceeds from a recognition of this
general law--in short, from rational intelligence. In
every inquiry what is conformable to nature, all turns
upon agreement with the essential constitution of the
being, and this essential constitution consists, in
the case of a man, simply in reason. One and the same
thing, therefore, always meant, whether, with Zeno,
life according to nature is spoken of as being in
harmony with oneself, or whether, following Cleanthes,
it is simply said to be the agreement of life with
nature, and whether, in the latter case, nature is
taken to mean the world at large, or is limited to
human nature in particular. In every case the meaning
is, that the life of the individual approximates to or
falls short of the goal of happiness, exactly in
proportion as it approaches to or departs from the
universal law of the world and the particular rational
nature of man. In a word, a rational life, an
agreement with the general course of the world,
constitutes virtue. The principle of the Stoic
morality might therefore be briefly expressed in the
sentence: Only virtue is good, and happiness consists
exclusively in virtue. If, however, following
Socrates, the good is defined as being what is useful,
then the sentence would run thus: Only Virtue is
useful; advantage cannot be distinguished from duty,
whilst to a bad man nothing is useful, since, in the
case of a rational being, good and evil does not
depend on what happens to him, but simply on his own
conduct. A view of life is here presented to us in
which happiness coincides with virtue, the good and
the useful with duty and reason. There is neither any
good independently of virtue, nor is there in virtue
and for virtue any evil.
The Stoics accordingly refused to admit the ordinary
distinction, sanctioned by popular opinion and the
majority of philosophers, between various kinds and
degrees of good; nor would they allow bodily
advantages and external circumstances to be included
among good things, together with mental and moral
qualities. A certain difference between goods they did
not indeed deny, and various kinds are mentioned by
them in their formal division of goods. But these
differences amount, in the end, to no more than this,
that whilst some goods are good and useful in
themselves, others are only subsidiary to them. The
existence of several equally primary goods appears to
the Stoics to be at variance with the conception of
the good. That only is a good, according to their
view, which has an unconditional value. That which has
a value only in comparison with something else, or as
leading to something else, does not deserve to be
called a good. The difference between what is good and
what is not good is not only a difference of degree,
but also one of kind; and what is not a good per se
can never be a good under any circumstances. The same
remarks apply to evil. That which is not in itself an
evil can never become so from its relation to
something else. Hence only that which is absolutely
good, or virtue, can be considered a good; and only
that which is absolutely bad, or vice, can be
considered an evil. All other things, however great
their influence may be on our state, belong to a class
of things neither good nor evil, but indifferent.
Neither health, nor riches, nor honor, not even life
itself, is a good; and just as little are the opposite
states--poverty, sickness, disgrace, and death--evils.
Both are in themselves indifferent a material which
may either be employed for good or else for evil.
The Academicians and Peripatetics were most vigorously
attacked by the Stoics for including among goods
external things which are dependent on chance. For how
can that be a good under any circumstances, which
bears no relation to man’s moral nature, and is even
frequently obtained at the cost of morality? If virtue
renders a man happy, it must render him perfectly
happy in himself, since no one can be happy who is not
happy altogether. Were anything which is not in man’s
power allowed to influence his happiness, it would
detract from the absolute worth of virtue, and man
would never be able to attain to that imperturbable
serenity of mind without which no happiness is
conceivable.
Least of all, can pleasure be considered a good, or be
regarded, as it was by Epicurus, as the ultimate and
highest object in life. He who places pleasure on the
throne makes a slave of virtue; he who considers
pleasure a good ignores the real conception of the
good and the peculiar value of virtue; he appeals to
feelings, rather than to actions; he requires
reasonable creatures to pursue what is unreasonable,
and souls nearly allied to God to go after the
enjoyments of the lower animals. Pleasure must never
be the object of pursuit, not even in the sense that
true pleasure is invariably involved in virtue. That
it no doubt is. It is true that there is always a
peculiar satisfaction, and a quiet cheerfulness and
peace of mind, in moral conduct, just as in immoral
conduct there is a lack of inward peace; and in this
sense it may be said that the wise man alone knows
what true and lasting pleasure is. But even the
pleasure afforded by moral excellence ought never to
be an object, but only a natural consequence, of
virtuous conduct; otherwise the independent value of
virtue is impaired.
Nor may pleasure be placed side by side with virtue,
as a part of the highest good, or be declared to be
inseparable from virtue. Pleasure and virtue are
different in essence and kind. Pleasure may be
immoral, and moral conduct may go hand in hand with
difficulties and pains. Pleasure is found among the
worst of men, virtue only amongst the good; virtue is
dignified, untiring, imperturbable; pleasure is
grovelling, effeminate, fleeting. Those who look upon
pleasure as a good are its slaves; those in whom
virtue reigns supreme control pleasure, and hold it in
check. In no sense can pleasure be allowed to weigh in
a question of morals; seeing it is not an
end-in-itself, but only the result of an action; not
a good, but something absolutely indifferent. The only
point on which the Stoics are not unanimous is,
whether every pleasure is contrary to nature, as the
stern Cleanthes, in the spirit of Cynicism, asserted,
or whether there is such a thing as a natural and
desirable pleasure. Virtue, on the other hand, needs
no extraneous additions, but contains in itself all
the conditions of happiness. The reward of virtuous
conduct, like the punishment of wickedness, consists
only in the character of those actions, one being
according to nature, the other contrary to nature. And
so unconditional is this self-sufficiency of virtue,
that the happiness which it affords is not increased
by length of time. Rational self-control is here
recognized as the only good; thereby man makes himself
independent of all external circumstances, absolutely
free, and inwardly satisfied.
The happiness of the virtuous man--and this is a very
marked feature in Stoicism--is thus more negative than
positive. It consists in independence and peace of
mind rather than in the enjoyment which moral conduct
brings with it. In mental disquietude--says Cicero,
speaking as a Stoic--consists misery; in composure,
happiness. How can he be deficient in happiness, he
inquires, whom courage preserves from care and fear,
and self-control guards from passionate pleasure and
desire? How can he fail to be absolutely happy who is
in no way dependent on fortune, but simply and solely
on himself? To be free from disquietude, says Seneca,
is the peculiar privilege of the wise; the advantage
which is gained from philosophy is, that of living
without fear, and rising superior to the troubles of
life. Far more emphatical than any isolated
expressions is the support which this negative view of
moral aims derives from the whole character of the
Stoic ethics, the one doctrine of the apathy of the
wise man sufficiently proving that freedom from
disturbances, an unconditional assurance, and
self-dependence, are the points on which these
philosophers lay especial value.
The Good, in as far as it is based on the general
arrangement of the world, to which the individual is
subordinate, appears to man in the character of Law.
Law being, however, the law of man’s own nature, the
Good becomes the natural object of man’s desire, and
meets his natural impulse. The conception of the Good
as law was a view never unfamiliar to moral
philosophy, but it was cultivated by the Stoics with
peculiar zeal; and forms one of the points on which
Stoicism subsequently came into contact, partly with
Roman jurisprudence, partly with the ethics of the
Jews and Christians. Moreover, as the Stoics
considered that the Reason which governs the world is
the general Law of all beings, so they recognized in
the moral demands of reason the positive and negative
aspects of the Law of God. Human law comes into
existence when man becomes aware of the divine law,
and recognizes its claims on him. Civil and moral law
are, therefore, commands absolutely imperative on
every rational being. No man can feel himself to be a
rational being without at the same time feeling
himself pledged to be moral. Obedience to this law is
imposed upon man not only by external authority, but
by virtue of his own nature. The good is for him that
which deserves to be pursued--the natural object of
man's will; on the other hand, evil is that against
which his will revolts. The former arouses his desire,
the latter his aversion: and thus the demands of
morality are called forth by the natural impulse of a
reasonable being, and are, at the same time, also the
object towards which that impulse is naturally
directed.
However simple this state of things may be to a purely
rational being, it must be remembered that man is not
purely rational. He has, therefore, irrational as well
as rational impulses. He is not originally virtuous,
but he becomes virtuous by overcoming his emotions.
Emotion or passion is a movement of mind contrary to
reason and nature, an impulse transgressing the right
mean. The Peripatetic notion, that certain emotions
are in accordance with nature, was flatly denied by
the Stoics. The seat of the emotions--and, indeed, of
all impulses and every activity of the soul--is man's
reason, that which is dominant. Emotion is that other
dominant state in which it is hurried into what is
contrary to nature by excess of impulse. Like virtue,
emotion is due to a change taking place
simultaneously, not to the effect of a separate
extraneous force. Imagination, therefore, alone calls
it into being, as it does impure in general. All
emotions arise from faults in judgment, from false
notions of good and evil, and may therefore be called,
in so many words, judgments or opinions;--avarice, for
instance, is a wrong opinion as to the value of money,
fear is a wrong opinion as regards future, trouble as
regards present ills. Still, as appears from the
general view of the Stoics respecting impulses, this
language does not imply that emotion is only a
theoretical condition. On the contrary, the effects of
a faulty imagination--the feelings and motions of
will, to which it gives rise--are expressly included
in its conception; nor is it credible, as Galenus
states, that this was only done by Zeno, and not by
Chrysippus. The Stoics, therefore, notwithstanding
their theory of necessity, did not originally assent
to the Socratic dictum, that no one does wrong
voluntarily. Younger members of the School may have
used the dictum as an excuse for human faults, fearing
lest, in allowing freedom to emotions, they should
admit that they were morally admissible and give up
the possibility of overcoming them. Nay more, as all
that proceeds from the will and impulse is voluntary,
so too emotions are also in our power; and it is for
us to say, in the case of convictions out of which
emotions arise, as in the case of every other
conviction, whether we will yield or withhold assent.
Just as little would they allow that only instruction
is needed in order to overcome emotions; for all
emotions arise, as they say, from lack of
self-control, and differ from errors in that they
assert themselves and oppose our better intelligence.
How irregular and irrational impulses arise in reason
was a point which the Stoics never made any serious
attempt to explain.
Emotions being called forth by imagination, their
character depends on the kind of imagination which
produces them. Now all impulses are directed to what
is good and evil, and consist either in pursuing what
appears to be a good, or in avoiding what appears to
be an evil. This good and this evil is sometimes a
present, and sometimes a future object. Hence there
result four chief classes of faulty imagination, and,
corresponding with them, four classes of emotions.
From an irrational opinion as to what is good there
arises pleasure, when it refers to things
present; desire, when it refers to things
future. A faulty opinion of present evils produces care;
of future evils, fear. Zeno had already
distinguished these four principal varieties of
emotions. The same division was adopted by his pupil
Aristo, and afterwards became quite general. Yet the
vagueness, already mentioned, appears in the Stoic
system in the definition of individual emotions. By
some, particularly by Chrysippus, the essence of
emotions is placed in the imagination which causes
them; by others, in the state of mind which the
imagination produces. The four principal classes of
emotions are again subdivided into numerous
subordinate classes, in the enumeration of which the
Stoic philosophers appear to have been more guided by
the use of language than by psychology.
In treating the subject of emotions in general, far
less importance was attached by the Stoics to
psychological accuracy than to considerations of moral
worth. That the result could not be very satisfactory,
follows from what has been already stated. Emotions
are impulses, overstepping natural limits, upsetting
the proper balance of the soul’s powers, contradicting
reason--in a word, they are failures, disturbances of
mental health, and, if indulged in, become chronic
diseases of the soul. Hence a Stoic demands their
entire suppression: true virtue can only exist where
this process has succeeded. As being contrary to
nature and symptoms of disease, the wise man must be
wholly free from them. When we have once learned to
value things according to their real worth, and to
discover everywhere nature’s unchanging law, nothing
will induce us to yield to emotion. Hence the teaching
of Plato and Aristotle, requiring emotions to be
regulated, but not uprooted, was attacked in the most
vigorous manner by these philosophers. A moderate
evil, they say, always remains an evil. What is faulty
and opposed to reason, ought never to be tolerated,
not even in the smallest degree. On the other hand,
when an emotion is regulated by and subordinated to
reason, it ceases to be an emotion, the term emotion
only applying to violent impulses, which are opposed
to reason. The statement of the Peripatetics, that
certain emotions are not only admissible, but are
useful and necessary, appears of course to the Stoics
altogether wrong. To them, only what is morally good
appears to be useful: emotions are, under all
circumstances, faults; and were an emotion to be
useful, virtue would be advanced by means of what is
wrong. The right relation, therefore, towards
emotions--indeed, the only one morally tenable--is an
attitude of absolute hostility. The wise man must be
emotionless. Pain he may feel, but, not regarding it
as an evil, he will suffer no affliction, and know no
fear. He may be slandered and ill-treated, but he
cannot be injured or degraded. Being untouched by
honor and dishonor, he has no vanity. To anger he
never yields, nor needs this irrational impulse, not
even for valor and the championship of right. But he
also feels no pity, and exercises no indulgence. For
how can he pity others for what he would not himself
consider an evil? How can he yield to a diseased
excitement for the sake of others, which he would not
tolerate for his own sake? If justice calls for
punishment, feelings will not betray him into
forgiveness. We shall subsequently have an opportunity
for learning the further application of these
principles.
Virtue is thus negatively defined as the being exempt
from emotions, as apathy. There is also a positive
side to supplement this negative view. Looking at the
matter of virtuous action, this may be said to
consist in subordination to the general law of nature;
looking at its manner, in rational
self-control. Virtue is exclusively a matter of
reason--in short, it is nothing else but rightly
ordered reason. To speak more explicitly, virtue
contains in itself two elements--one practical, the
other speculative. At the root, and as a condition of
all rational conduct, lies, according to the Stoic,
right knowledge. On this point they are at one with
the well-known Socratic doctrine, and with the
teaching of the Cynics and Megarians. Natural virtue,
or virtue acquired only by exercise, they reject
altogether. After the manner of Socrates, they define
virtue as knowledge, vice as ignorance, and insist on
the necessity of learning virtue. Even the avowed
enemy of all speculative inquiry, Aristo of Chios, was
on this point at one with the rest of the School. All
virtues were by him referred to wisdom, and,
consequently, he denied the claims of most to be
virtues at all.
However closely the Stoics cling to the idea that all
virtue is based on knowledge, and is in itself nothing
else but knowledge, they are not content with
knowledge, or with placing knowledge above practical
activity, as Plato and Aristotle had done. As we have
seen already, knowledge with them was only a means
towards rational conduct, and it is expressly
mentioned, as a deviation from the teaching of the
School, that Herillus of Carthage, Zeno’s pupil,
declared knowledge to be the end of life, and the only
unconditional good. Virtue may, it is true, be called
knowledge, but it is, at the same time, essentially
health and strength of mind, a right state of the soul
agreeing with its proper nature; and it is required of
man that he should never cease to labor and contribute
towards the common good. Thus, according to Stoic
principles, virtue is a combination of theory and
practice, in which action is invariably based on
intellectual knowledge, but, at the same time,
knowledge finds its object in moral conduct--it is, in
short, power of will based on rational understanding.
This definition must not, however, be taken to imply
that moral knowledge precedes will, and is only
subsequently referred to will, nor conversely that the
will only uses knowledge as a subsidiary instrument.
In the eyes of a Stoic, knowledge and will are not
only inseparable, but they are one and the same thing.
Virtue cannot be conceived without knowledge, nor
knowledge without virtue. The one, quite as much as
the other, is a right quality of the soul, or,
speaking more correctly, is the rightly endowed
soul,--reason, when it is as it ought to be. Hence
virtue may be described, with equal propriety, either
as knowledge or as strength of mind; and it is
irrelevant to inquire which of these two elements is
anterior in point of time.
But how are we to reconcile with this view the Stoic
teaching of a plurality of virtues and their mutual
relations? As the common root from which they spring,
Zeno, following Aristotle, regarded understanding,
Cleanthes, strength of mind, Aristo, at one time
health, at another the knowledge of good and evil.
Later teachers, after the time of Chrysippus, thought
that it consisted in knowledge or wisdom,
understanding by wisdom absolute knowledge, the
knowing all things, human and divine. From this common
root, a multiplicity of virtues was supposed to
proceed, which, after Plato's example, are grouped
round four principal virtues--intelligence, bravery,
justice, self-control. Intelligence consists in
knowing what is good and bad, and what is neither the
one nor the other, the indifferent; bravery, in
knowing what to choose, what to avoid, and what
neither to choose nor to avoid; or, substituting the
corresponding personal attitude for knowledge, bravery
is fearless obedience to the law of reason, both in
boldness and endurance. Self-control consists in
knowing what to choose, and what to eschew, and what
neither to choose nor eschew; justice, in knowing how
to give to everyone what is his due. In a
corresponding manner, the principal faults are traced
back to the conception of ignorance. Probably all
these definitions belong to Chrysippus. Other
definitions are attributed to his predecessors, some
more nearly, others more remotely, agreeing with him
in their conception of virtue. Within these limits, a
great number of individual virtues were distinguished,
their differences and precise shades of meaning being
worked out with all the pedantry which characterized
Chrysippus. The definitions of a portion of them have
been preserved by Diogenes and Stobaeus. In a similar
way, too, the Stoics carried their classification of
errors into the minutest details.
The importance attaching to this division of virtues,
the ultimate basis on which it rests, and the relation
which virtues bear, both to one another and to the
common essence of virtue, are topics upon which Zeno
never entered. Plutarch, at least, blames him for
treating virtues as many, and yet inseparable, and at
the same time for finding in all virtues only certain
manifestations of the understanding. Aristo attempted
to settle this point more precisely. According to his
view, virtue is in itself only one; in speaking of
many virtues, we only refer to the variety of objects
with which that one virtue has to do. The difference
of one virtue from another is not one of inward
quality, but depends on the external conditions under
which they are manifested; it only expresses a
definite relation to something else, or, in the
language of Herbart, an accidental aspect. The same
view would seem to be implied in the manner in which
Cleanthes determines the relations of the principal
virtues to one another. It was, however, opposed by
Chrysippus. The assumption of many virtues, he
believed, rested upon an inward difference; each
definite virtue, as also each definite fault, becoming
what it does by a peculiar change in the character of
the soul itself; in short, for a particular virtue to
come into being, it is not enough that the constituent
clement of all virtue should be directed towards a
particular object, but to the common element must be
superadded a further characteristic element, or
differentia; the several virtues being related to one
another, as the various species of one genus.
All virtues have, however, one and the same end, which
they compass in different ways, and all presuppose the
same moral tone and conviction, which is only to be
found where it is to be found perfect, and ceases to
exist the moment it is deprived of one of its
component parts. They are, indeed, distinct from one
another, each one having its own end, towards which it
is primarily directed; but, at the same time, they
again coalesce, inasmuch as none can pursue its own
end without pursuing that of the others at the same
time. Accordingly, no part of virtue can be separated
from its other parts. Where one virtue exists, the
rest exist also, and where there is one fault, there
all is faulty. Even each single virtuous action
contains all other virtues, for the moral tone of
which it is the outcome includes in itself all the
rest. What makes virtue virtue, and vice vice, is
simply and solely the intention. The will, although it
may lack the means of execution, is worth quite as
much as the deed; a wicked desire is quite as criminal
as the gratification of that desire. Hence only that
action can be called virtuous which is not only good
in itself, but which proceeds from willing the good;
and although, in the first instance, the difference
between the discharge and the neglect of duty depends
on the real agreement or disagreement of our actions
with the moral law, yet that alone can be said to be a
true and perfect discharge of duty which arises from a
morally perfect character.
Such a character, the Stoics held, must either exist
altogether, or not at all; for virtue is an
indivisible whole, which we cannot possess in part,
but must either have or not have. He who has a right
intention and a right appreciation of good and evil,
is virtuous: he who has not these requisites is
lacking in virtue: there is no third alternative.
Virtue admits neither of increase nor diminution, and
there is no mean between virtue and vice. This being
the case, and the value of an action depending wholly
on the intention, it follows, necessarily, that virtue
admits of no degrees. If the intention must be either
good or bad, the same must be true of actions; and if
a good intention or virtue has in it nothing bad, and
a bad intention has in it nothing good, the same is
true of actions. A good action is unconditionally
praiseworthy; a bad one, unconditionally blameworthy,
the former being only found where virtue exists pure
and entire; the latter, only where there is no virtue
at all. All good actions are, on the one hand,
according to the well-known paradox, equally good;
all bad actions, on the other, equally bad. The
standard of moral judgment is an absolute one; and
when conduct does not altogether conform to this
standard, it falls short of it altogether.
From what has been said, it follows that there can be
but one thoroughgoing moral distinction for all
mankind, the distinction between the virtuous and the
vicious; and that within each of these classes there
can be no difference in degree. He who possesses
virtue possesses it whole and entire; he who lacks it
lacks it altogether; and whether he is near or far
from possessing it is a matter of no moment. He who is
only a hand-breadth below the surface of the water
will be drowned just as surely as one who is five
hundred fathoms deep; he who is blind sees equally
little whether he will recover his sight tomorrow or
never. The whole of mankind are thus divided by the
Stoics into two classes--those who are wise and those
who are foolish; and these two classes are treated by
them as mutually exclusive, each one being complete in
itself. Among the wise no folly, among the foolish no
wisdom of any kind, is possible. The wise man is
absolutely free from faults and mistakes: all that he
does is right; in him all virtues center; he has a
right opinion on every subject, and never a wrong one,
nor, indeed, ever what is merely an opinion. The bad
man, on the contrary, can do nothing aright; he has
every kind of vice; he has no right knowledge, and is
altogether rude, violent, cruel, and ungrateful.
The Stoics delight in insisting upon the perfection of
the wise man, and contrasting with it the absolute
faultiness of the foolish man, in a series of
paradoxical assertions. The wise man only is free,
because he only uses his will to control himself; he
only is beautiful, because only virtue is beautiful
and attractive; he only is rich and happy, because
goods of the soul are the most valuable, true riches
consisting in being independent of wants. Nay, more,
he is absolutely rich, since he who has a right view
of everything has everything in his intellectual
treasury, and he who makes the right use of everything
bears to everything the relation of owner. The wise
only know how to obey, and they also only know how to
govern; they only are therefore kings, generals,
pilots; they only are orators, poets, and prophets;
and since their view of the Gods and their worship of
the Gods is the true one, only amongst them can true
piety he found--they are the only priests and friends
of heaven; all foolish men, on the contrary, are
impious, profane, and enemies of the Gods. Only the
wise man is capable of feeling gratitude, love, and
friendship, he only is capable of receiving a benefit,
nothing being of use or advantage to the foolish man.
To sum up, the wise man is absolutely perfect,
absolutely free from passion and want, absolutely
happy; as the Stoics conclusively assert, he in no way
falls short of the happiness of Zeus, since time, the
only point in which he differs from Zeus, does not
augment happiness at all. On the other hand, the
foolish man is altogether foolish, unhappy, and
perverse; or, in the expressive language of the
Stoics, every foolish man is a madman, he being a
madman who has no knowledge of himself, nor of what
most closely affects him.
This assertion is all the more trenchant because the
Stoics recognized neither virtue nor wisdom outside
their own system or one closely related to it, and
because they took a most unfavorable view of the moral
condition of their fellow-men. That they should do so
was inevitable from their point of view. A system
which sets up its own moral idea against current
notions so sharply as that of the Stoics can only be
the offspring of a thorough disapproval of existing
circumstances, and must, on the other hand, contribute
thereto. According to the Stoic standard, by far the
majority, indeed, almost the whole of mankind, belong
to the class of the foolish. If all foolish people are
equally and altogether bad, mankind must have seemed
to them to be a sea of corruption and vice, from
which, at best, but a few swimmers emerge at spots
widely apart. Man passes his life--such had already
been the complaint of Cleanthes--in wickedness. Only
here and there does one, in the evening of life, after
many wanderings, attain to virtue. And that this was
the common opinion among the successors of Cleanthes,
is witnessed by their constant complaints of the
depravity of the foolish, and of the rare occurrence
of a wise man.
No one probably has expressed this opinion more
frequently or more strongly than Seneca. We are
wicked, he says; we have been wicked; we shall be
wicked. Our ancestors complained of the decline of
morals; we complain of their decline; and posterity
will utter the very same complaint. The limits within
which morality oscillates are not far asunder; the
modes in which vice shows itself change, but its power
remains the same. All men are wicked; and he who has
as yet done nothing wicked is at least in a condition
to do it. All are thankless, avaricious, cowardly,
impious; all are mad. We have all done wrong--one in a
less, the other in a greater degree; and we shall all
do wrong to the end of the chapter. One drives the
other into folly, and the foolish are too numerous to
allow the individual to improve. He who would be angry
with the vices of men. instead of pitying their
faults, would never stop. So great is the amount of
iniquity!
No doubt the age in which Seneca lived afforded ample
occasion for such effusions, but his predecessors must
have found similar occasions in their own days.
Indeed, all the principles of the Stoic School, when
consistently developed, made it impossible to consider
the great majority of men as anything else than a mass
of fools and sinners. From this sweeping verdict, even
the most distinguished names were not excluded. If
asked for examples of wisdom, they would point to
Socrates, Diogenes, Antisthenes, and, in later times,
to Cato; but not only would they deny philosophic
virtue, as Plato had done before them, to the greatest
statesmen and heroes of early times, but they would
deny to them all and every kind of virtue. Even the
admission that general faults belong to some in a
lower degree than to others can hardly he reconciled
with their principle of the equality of all who are
not wise.
The two moral states being thus at opposite
poles, a gradual transition from one to the other is,
of course, out of the question. There may be a
progress from folly and wickedness in the direction of
wisdom, but the actual passage from one to the other
must be momentary and instantaneous. Those who are
still progressing belong, without exception, to the
class of the foolish; and one who has lately become
wise is in the first moment unconscious of his new
state. The transition takes place so rapidly, and his
former state affords so few points of contact with the
one on which he has newly entered, that the mind does
not keep pace with the change, and only becomes
conscious of it by subsequent experience.
In this picture of the wise man, the moral idealism of
the Stoic system attained its zenith. A virtuous will
appears here so completely sundered from all outward
conditions of life, so wholly free from all the
trammels of natural existence, and the individual has
become so completely the organ of universal law, that
it may be asked, What right has such a being to call
himself a person? How can such a being be imagined as
a man living among fellow-men? Nor was this question
unknown to the Stoics themselves. Unless they are
willing to allow that their theory was practically
impossible, and their ideal scientifically untenable,
how could they escape the necessity of showing that it
might be reconciled with the wants of human life and
the conditions of reality? Let the attempt be once
made, however, and withal they would be forced to look
for some means of adapting it to those very feedings
and opinions towards which their animosity had
formerly been so great. Nor could the attempt be long
delayed. Daily a greater value was attached to the
practical working of their system, and to its
agreement with general opinion. The original direction
of Stoic morality aimed at the absolute and
unconditional submission of the individual to the law
of the universe, yet, in developing that theory, the
rights of the individual asserted themselves
unmistakably. From this confluence of opposite
currents arose a deviation from the rigid type of the
Stoic system, some varieties of which, in the
direction of the ordinary view of life, deserve now
further consideration.
Chapter XI. The Stoic Theory of Morals as Modified
by Practical Needs.
THE Stoic theory of Ethics is entirely rooted
in the proposition, that only virtue is a good and
only vice an evil. This proposition, however,
frequently brought the Stoics into collision with
current views; nor was it without its difficulties for
their own system. In the first place, virtue is made
to depend for its existence upon certain conditions,
and to lead to certain results, from which it is
inseparable. These results, we have already seen, were
included by the Stoics in the list of goods. Moreover,
virtue is said to be the only good, because only what
is according to nature is a good, and rational conduct
is for man the only thing according to nature. But can
this be so absolutely and unconditionally stated?
According to the Stoic teaching the instinct of
self-preservation being the primary impulse, does not
this instinct manifestly include the preservation and
advancement of outward life? The Stoics, therefore,
could not help including physical goods and activities
among things according to nature--for instance,
health, a right enjoyment of the senses, and such
like. Practically, too, the same admission was forced
upon them by the consideration that, if there is no
difference in value between things in themselves,
rational choice--and, indeed, all acting on
motives--is impossible. At the same time, they reject
the notion that what is first according to nature must
therefore be perfect or good, just as in theory they
allow that the source of knowledge, but not truth
itself, is derived from the senses. When man has once
recognized the universal law of action, he will,
according to their view, think little of what is
sensuous and individual, and only look upon it as an
instrument in the service of virtue and reason.
Still, there remains the question, How can this be
possible? and this is no easy one to answer. The
contemporary opponents of the Stoics already took
exception to the way in which the first demands of
nature were by them excluded from the aims of a life
according to nature; and we, too, cannot suppress a
feeling of perplexity at being told that all duties
aim at attaining what is primarily according to
nature, but that what is according to nature must not
be looked upon as the aim of our actions; since not
that which is simply according to nature, but the
rational choice and combination of what is according
to nature constitutes the good. Even if the Stoics
pretend to dispose of this difficulty, they cannot, at
least, fail to see that whatever contributes to bodily
well-being must have a certain positive value, and
must be desirable in all cases in which no higher good
suffers in consequence; and, conversely, that whatever
is opposed to bodily well-being, when higher duties
are not involved, must have a negative value, and,
consequently, deserve to be avoided. Such objects and
actions they would not, however, allow to be included
in the class of goods which are absolutely valuable.
It was therefore a blending of Peripatetic with Stoic
teaching when Herillus, the fellow-student of
Cleanthes, enumerated bodily and outward goods as
secondary and subsidiary aims besides virtue.
Nor were the Stoics minded to follow the contemporary
philosopher. Aristo of Chios (who in this point, too,
endeavored to place their School on the platform of
the Cynic philosophy), in denying any difference in
value between things morally indifferent and in making
the highest aim in life consist in indifference to all
external things. Virtue with them bears, in comparison
with the Cynic virtue, a more positive character, that
of an energetic will; they, therefore, required some
definite relation to the outward objects and
conditions of this activity which should regulate the
choosing or rejecting--or, in other words, the
practical decision. Accordingly, they divided things
indifferent into three classes. To the first class
belong all those things which, from a moral or
absolute point of view, are neither good nor evil, but
yet which have a certain value; no matter whether this
value belongs to them properly, because they are in
harmony with human nature, or whether it belongs to
them improperly, because they are means for advancing
moral and natural life, or whether it belongs to them
on both grounds. The second class includes everything
which, either by itself or in its relation to higher
aims, is opposed to nature and harmful. The third,
things which, even in this conditional sense, have
neither positive nor negative value. The first class
bears the name of things preferential, or things
desirably; the second is the class of things to be
eschewed; the third is the class of things
intermediate. The last is called, in the strict sense,
indifferent. It includes not only what is really
indifferent, but whatever has such a slight negative
or positive value that it neither enkindles desire nor
aversion. Hence the terms preferential and eschewed
are defined to mean respectively that which has an
appreciable positive or negative value. Under things
preferential, the Stoics include partly mental
qualities and conditions, such as talents and skill,
even progress towards virtue, in as far as it is not
yet virtue; partly bodily advantage--beauty, strength,
health, life itself; partly external goods--riches,
honor, noble birth, relations, &c. Under things to
be eschewed, they understand the opposite things and
conditions; under things indifferent, whatever has no
appreciable influence on our choice, such as the
question whether the number of hairs on the head is
even or uneven; whether I pick up a piece of waste
paper from the floor, or leave it; whether one piece
of money or another is used in payment of a debt. Yet
they drew a sharp distinction between the purely
relative value of things preferential, and the
absolute value of things morally good. Only the latter
are really allowed to be called good, because they
only, under all circumstances, are useful and
necessary. Of things morally indifferent, on the other
hand, the best may, under certain circumstances, be
bad, and the worst--sickness, poverty, and the
like--may, under certain circumstances, be useful.
Just as little would they allow that the independence
of the wise man suffered by the recognition outside
himself of a class of things preferential. For the
wise man, said Chrysippus, uses such things without
requiring them. Nevertheless, the admission of classes
of things to be preferred and to be declined obviously
undermines their doctrine of the good. Between what is
good and what is evil, a third group is introduced, of
doubtful character; and since we have seen the term
indifferent is only applied to this group in its more
extended meaning, it became impossible for them to
refuse to apply the term good to things desirable, or
to exclude unconditionally from the highest good many
of the things which they were in the habit of
pronouncing indifferent. Nor was this concession
merely the yielding of a term, as will appear when
particular instances are considered. Not only may
Seneca be heard, in Aristotelian manner, defending
external possessions as aids to virtue--not only
Hecato, and even Diogenes, uttering ambiguous
sentences as to permitted and forbidden gains--not
only Panaetius giving expression to much that falls
short of Stoic severity--but even Chrysippus avows
that in his opinion it is silly not to desire health,
wealth, and freedom from pain, and that a statesman
may treat honor and wealth as real goods; adding that
the whole Stoic School agrees with him in thinking it
no disparagement for a wise man to follow a profession
which lies under a stigma in the common opinion of
Greece. He did not even hesitate to assert that it is
better to live irrationally than not live at all. It
is impossible to conceal the fact that, in attempting
to adapt their system to general opinion and to the
conditions of practical life, the Stoics were driven
to make admissions strongly at variance with their
previous theories. It may hence be gathered with
certainty that, in laying down those theories, they
had overstrained a point.
By means of this doctrine of things to be preferred
and things to be eschewed, a further addition was made
to the conception of duty. Under duty, or what is
proper, we have already seen, the Stoics understand
rational action in general, which becomes good
conduct, by being done with a right intention. The
conception of duty, therefore, contains in itself the
conception of virtuous conduct, and is used primarily
to express what is good or rational. Duty thus appears
to have a twofold meaning, in consequence of the
twofold characters of things desirable and things
good. If the good were the only permitted object of
desire, there would, of course, be but one duty--that
of realizing the good; and the various actions which
contribute to this result would only be distinguished
by their being employed on a different material, but
not in respect of their moral value. But if, besides
what is absolutely good, there are things relatively
good, things not to be desired absolutely, but only in
cases in which they may be pursued without detriment
to the absolute good or virtue--if, moreover, besides
vice, as the absolute evil, there are also relative
evils, which we have reason to avoid in the same
cases--the extent of our duties is increased likewise;
a number of conditional duties are placed by the side
of duties unconditional, differing from the latter in
that they aim at pursuing things to be preferred, and
avoiding things to be eschewed. From this platform,
all that accords with nature is regarded as proper, or
a duty in the more extended sense of the term; and the
conception of propriety is extended to include plants
and animals. Proper and dutiful actions are then
divided into those which are always such and those
which are only such under peculiar circumstances--the
former being called perfect, the latter intermediate
duties; and it is stated, as a peculiarity of the
latter, that, owing to circumstances, a course of
conduct may become a duty which would not have been a
duty without those peculiar circumstances. In the
wider sense of the term, every action is proper or in
accordance with duty which consists in the choice of a
thing to be preferred and in avoiding a thing to be
eschewed. On the other hand, a perfect duty is only
fulfilled by virtuous action. A virtuous life and a
wish to do good constitute the only perfect duty.
Some confusion is introduced into this teaching by the
fact that in setting up the standard for
distinguishing perfect from imperfect duties, the
Stoics sometimes look at the real, sometimes at the
personal value, of actions, without keeping these two
aspects distinct. They therefore use the terms perfect
and imperfect sometimes to express the difference
between conditional and unconditional duties; at other
times, to express that between morality and law. Far
worse than the formal defect is the grouping in this
division under the conception of duty things of the
most varied moral character. If once things which have
only a conditional value are admitted within the
circle of duties, what is there to prevent their being
defended, in the practical application of the Stoic
teaching, on grounds altogether repugnant to the
legitimate consequences of the Stoic principles?
In accordance with these admissions, the Stoic system
sought in another respect to meet facts and practical
wants by abating somewhat from the austerity of its
demands. Consistently carried out, those demands
require the unconditional extirpation of the whole
sensuous nature, such as was originally expressed by
the demand for apathy. But just as the stricter Stoic
theory of the good was modified by the admission of
the thing to be preferred, so this demand was modified
in two ways; the first elements of the forbidden
emotions were allowed under other names; and whilst
emotions were still forbidden, certain mental
affections were permitted, and even declared to be
desirable. Taking the first point, it is allowed by
the Stoics that the wise man feels pain, and that at
certain things he does not remain wholly calm. This
admission shows that their system was not identical
with that of the Cynics. It is not required that men
should be entirely free from all mental affections,
but only that they should refuse assent to them, and
not suffer them to obtain the mastery. With regard to
the other point, they propound the doctrine of
rational dispositions, which, as distinct from
emotions, are to be found in the wise man, and in the
wise man only. Of these rational dispositions, they
distinguish three chief besides several subordinate
varieties. Although this admission was intended to
vindicate the absence of emotions in the wise man,
since the permitted feelings are not emotions, still
it made the boundary line between emotions and
feelings so uncertain that in practice the
sharply-defined contrast between the wise and the
foolish threatened well nigh to disappear altogether.
This danger appears more imminent when we observe the
perplexity in which the Stoics were placed when asked
to point out the wise man in experience. For not only
do opponents assert that, according to their own
confession, no one, or as good as no one, can be found
in actual history who altogether deserves that high
title, but even their own admissions agree therewith.
They describe even Socrates, Diogenes, and Antisthenes
as not completely virtuous, but only as travelers
towards virtue. It was of little avail to point to
Hercules or Ulysses, or with Posidonius, to the
mythical golden age, in which the wise are said to
have ruled. The pictures of those heroes would have to
be changed altogether, to bring them into harmony with
the wise man of the Stoics; and Posidonius might be
easily disposed of on Stoic principles, by the
rejoinder that virtue and wisdom are things of free
exercise, and, since free exercise was wanting in the
case of the first men, their condition can only have
been a state of unconscious ignorance, and not one of
perfection. If, in reality, there are no wise men, the
division of men into wise and foolish falls at once to
the ground: all mankind belong to the class of fools;
the conception of the wise man is an unreal fancy. It
becomes, then, difficult to maintain the assertion
that all fools are equally foolish, and all the wise
are equally wise. If, instead of producing real
wisdom, philosophy can only produce progress towards
wisdom, it can hardly be expected to take such a
modest estimate of its own success as to allow that
there is no real distinction between a zealous student
and a bigoted despiser of its doctrines.
It was therefore natural that the Stoics,
notwithstanding their own maxims, found themselves
compelled to recognize differences among the bad and
differences among good. In reference to their system
these differences were, indeed, made to depend in the
case of the bad upon the greater or less difficulty of
healing the moral defects, or, in the case of the
good, upon qualities morally indifferent. It was also
natural that they should so nearly identify the state
of progress towards wisdom, the only really existing
state, with wisdom that it could hardly be
distinguished therefrom. If there is a stage of
progress in which a man is free from all emotions,
discharges all his duties, knows all that is
necessary, and is even secure against the danger of
relapse, such a stage cannot be distinguished from
wisdom, either by its want of experience or by the
absence of a clear knowledge of oneself. For has it
not been frequently asserted that happiness is not
increased by length of time, and that the wise man is
at first not conscious of his wisdom? If, however, the
highest stage of approximation to wisdom is supposed
still to fall short of wisdom, because it is not sure
of its continuance, and though free from mental
diseases, it is not free from emotions, how, it may be
asked, do these passing emotions differ from the
mental affections which are found in the wise man? Is
there any real distinction between them? If the
progressing candidate has attained to freedom from
diseased mental states, is the danger of a relapse
very great? Besides, the Stoics were by no means
agreed that the really wise man is free from all
danger. Cleanthes held with the Cynics that virtue can
never be lost; Chrysippus admitted that, in certain
cases, it is defectible. After all this admission is
only one among many traits which prove that the Stoics
were obliged to abate from the original severity of
their demands.
Chapter XII. Applied Moral Science.
ALL that has hitherto been stated has regard
to the general principles only of the Stoics touching
the end and the conditions of moral action. Whether
the mere exposition of principles be enough, or
whether the practical application of these principles
to the special relations of life does not also form
part of moral science--is a question as to which the
Stoic School was not originally unanimous. Aristo, a
Cynic on this as on other points, was of opinion that
this whole branch of moral science is useless and
unnecessary; the philosopher must confine himself
exclusively to things which have a practical value,
the fundamental ground of morality. Within the Stoic
School, however, this view did not gain much support.
Even Cleanthes, who otherwise agreed with Aristo, did
not deny the value of the application of theory to
details, provided the connection of details with
general principles were not lost sight of. Nor can
there be any doubt that, after the time of Chrysippus,
details engrossed much of the attention of the Stoic
philosophers. Posidonius enumerates, as belonging to
the province of moral philosophy, precept,
exhortation, and advice. His teacher, Panaetius, had
discussed the hortatory side of morality in three
books on duties, which are imitated in Cicero’s
well-known treatise. The division of ethics
attributed to Diogenes, and by him referred to
Chrysippus, leaves place for such discussions; and,
not to mention Aristo’s opposition, which supposes the
existence of applied moral science, the example of his
fellow-student Persaeus, whose precepts for a science
of banqueting have been already referred to, proves
how early practical ethics had obtained a footing
within the Stoic School. Moreover, the elaborate
theory of virtue propounded by Chrysippus and his
followers can hardly have failed to include many of
the principal occurrences in life. Thus a number of
particular precepts are known to us, which are partly
quoted by other writers as belonging to the Stoics,
and are partly to be found in the pages of Seneca,
Epictetus, and Marcus Aurelius, and in Cicero’s
treatise on duties. Indeed, the Stoics were the first
who went at all deeply into the subject of casuistry.
At a later epoch, when more general questions had been
settled by Chrysippus, the preference for particular
inquiries within the domain of applied moral science
appears to have increased among the Stoics. Probably
none but the later members of the School advanced the
unscientific assertion that we ought to confine
ourselves to precepts for particular cases, since only
these have any practical value.
In this extension of the moral theory, besides the
desire for scientific completeness, the endeavor may
also be observed to subordinate all sides of human
activity to moral considerations. In the virtuous man,
as the Stoics held, everything becomes virtue; and
hence everything is included in moral philosophy.
Thereby, without doubt, the Stoic School contributed
in no small decree towards settling and defining moral
ideas, not only for its immediate contemporaries. but
also for all subsequent times. Nevertheless, the more
the teaching of the School entered into the details of
every-day life, the more impossible it became to
prevent practical considerations from overriding the
natural severity of Stoic principles, or to keep the
strictness of scientific procedure from yielding to
considerations of experience.
The order and division which the Stoics adopted for
discussing details in the hortatory part of moral
science are not known to us; nor, indeed, is it known
whether that order was uniform in all cases. It will
be most convenient for the purpose of our present
description to distinguish, in the first place, those
points which refer to the moral activity of the
individual as such, and afterwards to go on to those
which relate to social life. Subsequently, the
teachings of the Stoics on the relation of man to the
course of the world and to necessity will engage our
attention.
It was in keeping with the whole tone of the Stoic
system to devote, in ethics, more attention to the
conduct and duties of the individual than had been
done by previous philosophy. Not that previous
philosophers had altogether ignored this side. Indeed,
Aristotle, in his investigations into individual
virtue, had been led to inquire carefully into
individual morality. Still, with Aristotle, the
influence of classic antiquity on the border-land of
which he stands was sufficiently strong to throw the
individual into the background as compared with the
community, and to subordinate ethics to politics. In
the post-Aristotelian philosophy, this relation was
exactly reversed. With the decline of public life in
Greece, intellectual interest in the state declined
also; and, in equal degree, the personality of the
individual and circumstances of private life came into
prominence. This feature may be already noticed in
some of the older Schools, for instance, in the
Academy and Peripatetic School. The Peripatetic, in
particular, had, in the time of its first adherents,
traveled far on the road which the founder had struck
out. Among the Stoics, the same feature was required
by the whole spirit of their system. If happiness
depends upon man's internal state and nothing external
has power to affect it, the science which professes to
lead man to happiness must primarily busy itself with
man's moral nature. It can only consider human society
in as far as action for society forms part of the
moral duty of the individual. Hence, in the Stoic
philosophy, researches into the duties of the
individual occupy a large space, and there is a
corresponding subordination of politics. These duties
form the subject of by far the greater part of the
applied moral science of the Stoics: and it has been
already set forth how minutely they entered in that
study into possible details. At the same time, the
scientific harvest resulting from these researches is
by no means in proportion to their extent.
Confining our attention to the two first books of
Cicero’s work, De Officiis, to form some idea
of the treatise of Panaetius on duties, we find, after
a few introductory remarks, morality as such
described, according to the scheme of the four
cardinal virtues (i. 5-42). In discussing the first of
these, intelligence, love of research is recommended,
and useless subtlety is deprecated. Justice and
injustice are next discussed in all their various
forms, due regard being had to the cases of ordinary
occurrence in life. Liberality, kindness, and
benevolence are treated as subdivisions of justice;
and this leads to a consideration of human society in
all its various forms (c. 16-18, 60). Turning next to
bravery (18, 61), the philosopher draws attention to
the fact that bravery is inseparably connected with
justice. He then describes it partly as it appears in
the forms of magnanimity and endurance, regardless of
external circumstances, partly in the form of
energetic courage; and, in so doing, he discusses
various questions which suggest themselves, such as
the nature of true and false courage, military and
civil courage, and the exclusion of anger from valor
Lastly, the object of the fourth chief virtue (c. 27)
is described, in general terms, as what is proper, and
the corresponding state as propriety, both in
controlling the impulses of the senses, in jest and
play, and in the whole personal bearing. The peculiar
demands made by individual nature, by time of life, by
civil position, are discussed. Even outward
proprieties--of speech and conversation, of domestic
arrangement, tact in behavior, honorable and
dishonorable modes of life--do not escape attention.
In the second book of his work, Cicero considers the
relation of interest to duty; and having proved, at
length, that most that is advantageous and
disadvantageous is brought on us by other men, he
turns to the means by which we may gain the support of
others, and by which affection, trust, and admiration
may be secured. He reviews various kinds of services
for individuals and the state, and embraces the
opportunity to give expression to his abhorrence of
despotism and republican servility to the people. The
principles on which this review is conducted are such
that objection can rarely be taken to them from the
platform of modern morality. Yet the Stoic bias is
unmistakably present in the conception and support of
the rules of life, and particularly in the definitions
of various virtues; few of the moral judgments,
however, are other than might have been expressed from
the platform of the Platonic and Aristotelian ethics.
The same remark holds good of some other recorded
points by means of which the Stoics gave a further
expansion to their picture of the wise man. Revolting
as their tenets at times appear, there is yet little
in their application that deviated from the moral
ideas generally current.
More peculiar, and at the same time more startling, is
another feature about the Stoics. Let not too much be
made of the fact that they, under certain
circumstances, permitted a lie. Were not Socrates and
Plato, at least, of the same opinion? And, to be
frank, we must admit that, although in this respect
moral theories are strict enough, yet practice is
commonly far too lax now. Very repulsive, however, are
many assertions attributed to the Stoics, respecting
the attitude of the wise man to the so-called
intermediate things. Was not the very independence of
externals, the indifference to everything but the
moral state, which found expression in the doctrine of
things indifferent and of the wise man's apathy, at
the root of that imperfection of life and principle
which is so prominent in the Cynic School, the parent
School of the Stoics? Granting that in the Stoic
School this imperfection was toned down and
supplemented by other elements, still the tendency
thereto was too deeply rooted from its origin, and too
closely bound up with its fundamental view of life, to
be ever properly eradicated. It did not require,
indeed, a Cynic life from its members; nay, more, it
avowed that, except in rare cases, such a life ought
not to be followed; still the Cynic’s life was its
ideal; and when it asserted that it was not necessary
for a wise man to be a Cynic, it implied that, if once
a Cynic, he would always be a Cynic. Stoicism took for
its patterns Antisthenes and Diogenes quite as much as
Socrates; even those who held, with Seneca, that a
philosopher ought to accommodate himself to prevailing
customs, and, from regard to others, do what he would
not himself approve, did not therefore cease to bestow
their highest admiration on Diogenes’s independence of
wants, not-withstanding his eccentricities. Move
consistent thinkers even approximated to Cynicism in
their moral precepts, and in later times a School of
younger Cynics actually grew out of the Stoic School.
Bearing, as the Stoics did, this close relationship to
the Cynics, it cannot astonish us to find amongst them
many instances of the most revolting traits in
Cynicism. Their contempt for cultured habits and
violation of right feelings fully justify the
righteous indignation of their opponents. Chrysippus
regarded many things as perfectly harmless in which
the religious feeling of Greece saw pollution, and
pleaded in defense of his opinion the example of
animals, to show that they were according to nature.
The care for deceased relatives he not only proposed
to limit to the simplest mode of burial, but would
have it altogether put aside; and he made the horrible
suggestion, which he even described in full, of using
for purposes of nourishment the flesh of amputated
limbs and the corpses of the nearest relatives. Great
offense, too, was given by the Stoics, and, in
particular, by Chrysippus, in their treatment of the
relation of the sexes to each other; nor can it be
denied that some of their language on this subject
sounds exceedingly offensive. The Cynic assertion,
that anything which is in itself allowed may be
mentioned plainly and without a periphrasis, is also
attributed to the Stoics. By his proposals for the
dress of women, Zeno offended against propriety and
modesty, and both he and Chrysippus advocated
community of wives in their state of wise men. It is,
moreover, asserted that the Stoics raised no objection
to the prevalent profligacy and the trade in
unchastity, nor to the still worse vice of unnatural
crime. Marriage among the nearest relatives was held
to be consonant to nature by the leaders of the
School; and the atrocious shamelessness of Diogenes
found supporters in Chrysippus, perhaps, too, in Zeno.
It would, however, be doing the Stoics a great
injustice to take these statements for more than
theoretical conclusions drawn from the principles to
which they were pledged. The moral character of Zeno,
Cleanthes, and Chrysippus is quite above suspicion. It
seems, therefore, strange that they should have felt
themselves compelled to admit in theory what strikes
the natural feeling with horror. It cannot, however,
be unconditionally accepted that the statements laid
to their charge as they used them imply all that
historians find in them. Far from it; of some of their
statements it may be said not only that they do not
justify conduct recognized to be immoral, but that
they are directed against actions customarily allowed,
the argument being, that between such actions and
actions admittedly immoral there is no real
difference. This remark applies, in particular, to
Zeno’s language on unnatural vice. It was not,
therefore, in opposition to the older Stoics, or a
denial of their maxim that love is permitted to a wise
man, for the younger Stoics to condemn most explicitly
any and every form of unchastity, and, in particular,
the worst form of all, unnatural vice. In the same
way, the language permitting marriage between those
nearest of kin, when examined, is very much milder
than it seems. And Zeno's proposition for a community
of wives may be fairly laid to the charge of Plato,
and excused by all the charitable excuses of which
Plato is allowed the benefit.
Taking the most unprejudiced view of the Stoic
propositions, there are enough of them to arouse
extreme dislike, even if they could, without
difficulty, be deduced from the fundamental principles
of the system. A moral theory which draws such a sharp
distinction between what is without, and what is
within, that it regards the latter as alone essential,
the former as altogether indifferent, which attaches
no value to anything except virtuous intention, and
places the highest value in being independent of
everything--such a moral theory must of necessity
prove wanting, whenever the business of morality
consists in using the senses as instruments for
expressing the mind, and in raising natural impulses
to the sphere of free will. If its prominent features
allow less to the senses than naturally belongs to
them, there is a danger that, in particular cases in
which intentions are not so obvious, the moral
importance of actions will often be ignored, and such
actions treated as indifferent.
The same observation will have to be made with regard
to the positions which the Stoics laid down in
reference to social relations. Not that it was their
intention to detach man from his natural relation to
other men. On the contrary, they hold that the further
man carries the work of moral improvement in himself,
the stronger he will feel drawn to society. But by the
introduction of the idea of society, opposite
tendencies arise in their ethics--one towards
individual independence, the other in the direction of
a well-ordered social life. The former tendency is
the earlier one, and continues to predominate
throughout; still, the latter was not surreptitiously
introduced--nay, more, it was the logical result of
the Stoic principles, and to the eye of an Epicurean
must have seemed a distinctive feature of Stoicism. In
attributing absolute value only to rational thought
and will, Stoicism had declared man to be independent
of anything external, and, consequently, of his
fellow-men. But since this value only attaches to
rational thought and intention, the freedom of the
individual also involves the recognition of the
community, and brings with it the requirement that
everyone must subordinate his own wishes to the wishes
and needs of others. Rational conduct and thought can
only then exist when the conduct of the individual is
in harmony with general law. General law is the same
for all rational beings. All rational beings must
therefore aim at the same end. and recognize
themselves subject to the same law. All must feel
themselves portions of one connected whole. Man must
not live for himself, but for society.
This connection between the individual and society is
clearly set forth by the Stoics. The desire for
society, they hold, is immediately involved in reason.
By the aid of reason, man feels himself a part of a
whole, and, consequently, is bound to subordinate his
private interests to the interests of the whole. As
like always attracts like, this remark holds true of
everything endowed with reason, since the rational
soul is in all cases identical. From the consciousness
of this unity, the desire for society at once arises
in individuals endowed with reason. They are all in
the service of reason; there is, therefore, for all,
but one right course and one law, and they all
contribute to the general welfare in obeying this law.
The wise man, as a Stoic expresses it, is never a
private man.
At other times, social relations were explained by the
theory of final causes. Whilst everything else exists
for the sake of what is endowed with reason,
individual beings endowed with reason exist for the
sake of each other. Their social connection is
therefore a direct natural command. Towards animals we
never stand in a position to exercise justice, nor yet
towards ourselves. Justice can only be exercised
towards other men and towards God. On the combination
of individuals and their mutual support rests all
their power over nature. A single man by himself would
be the most helpless of creatures.
The consciousness of this connection between all
rational beings finds ample expression in Marcus
Aurelius, the last of the Stoics. The possession of
reason is, with him, love of society (vi. 14; x. 2).
National beings can only be treated on a social
footing (vi. 23 ), and can only feel happy themselves
when working for the community (viii. 7); for all
rational beings are related to one another (iii. 4),
all form one social unit, of which each individual is
an integral part (ix. 23): one body, of which every
individual is an organic member (ii. 1; vii. 13).
Hence the social instinct is a primary instinct in man
(vii. 55), every manifestation of which contributes,
either directly or indirectly, to the good of the
whole (ix. 23). Our fellow-men ought to be loved from
the heart. They ought to be benefited, not for the
sake of outward decency, but because the benefactor is
penetrated with the joy of benevolence, and thereby
benefits himself. Whatever hinders union with others
has a tendency to separate the members from the body,
from which all derive their life (viii. 55); and he
who estranges himself from one of his fellow-men
voluntarily severs himself from the stock of mankind
(xi. 23). We shall presently see that the language
used by the philosophic emperor is quite in harmony
with the Stoic principles.
In relation to our fellow-men, two fundamental points
are insisted on by the Stoics--the duty of justice and
the duty of mercy. Cicero, without doubt following
Panaetius, describes these two virtues as the bonds
which keep human society together, and, consequently,
gives to each an elaborate treatment. In expanding
these duties, the Stoics were led by the fundamental
principles of their system to most distracting
consequences. On the one hand, they required from
their wise men that strict justice which knows no pity
and can make no allowances; hence their ethical system
had about it an air of austerity, and an appearance of
severity and cruelty. On the other hand, their
principle of the natural connection of all mankind
imposed on them the practice of the most extended and
unreserved charity, of beneficence, gentleness,
meekness, of an unlimited benevolence, and a readiness
to forgive in all cases in which forgiveness is
possible. This last aspect of the Stoic teaching
appears principally in the later Stoics--in Seneca,
Epictetus, Marcus Aurelius, and Musonius; and it is
quite possible that they may have given more
prominence to it than their predecessors. But the fact
is there, that this aspect is due. not only to the
peculiar character of these individuals, but is based
on the spirit and tone of the whole system.
The question then naturally arises, how these two
opposites may be reconciled--how stern justice may be
harmonized with forgiveness and mercy. Seneca, who
investigated the question fully, replies: Not
severity, but only cruelty, is opposed to mercy; for
no one virtue is opposed to another: a wise man will
always help another in distress, but without sharing
his emotion, without feeling misery or compassion; he
will not indulge, but he will spare, advise, and
improve; he will not remit punishments in cases in
which he knows them to be deserved, but, from a sense
of justice, he will take human weakness into
consideration in allotting punishments, and make every
possible allowance for circumstances. Every difficulty
is not, indeed, removed by these statements; still,
those which remain apply more to the Stoic demand for
apathy than to the reconciliation of the two virtues
which regulate our relations to our fellow-men.
The society for which all rational beings are intended
will naturally be found to exist principally among
those who have become alive to their rational nature
and destiny--in other words, among the wise. All who
are wise and virtuous are friends, because they agree
in their views of life, and because they all love one
another's virtue. Thus every action of a wise man
contributes to the well-being of every other wise
man--or, as the Stoics pointedly express it, if a wise
man only makes a rational movement with his finger, he
does a service to all wise men throughout the world.
On the other hand, only a wise man knows how to love
properly; true friendship only exists between wise
men. Only the wise man possesses the art of making
friends, since love is only won by love. If, however,
true friendship is a union between the good and the
wise, its value is thereby at once established; and
hence it is distinctly enumerated among goods by the
Stoics.
On this point, difficulties reappear. How can this
need of society be reconciled with the wise man's
freedom from wants? If the wise man is
self-sufficient, how can another help him? How can he
stand in need of such help? The answers given by
Seneca are not satisfactory. To the first question, he
replies, that none but a wise man can give the right
inducement to a wise man to call his powers into
exercise. He meets the second by saying, that a wise
man suffices himself for happiness, but not for life.
Everywhere the wise man finds inducements to virtuous
action; if friendship is not a condition of happiness,
it is not a good at all. Nor are his further
observations more satisfactory. The wise man, he says,
does not wish to be without friends, but still
he can be without friends. But the question is
not whether he can be, but whether he can be
without loss of happiness. If the question so put is
answered in the negative, it follows that the wise man
is not altogether self-sufficing; if in the
affirmative--and a wise man, as Seneca affirms, will
bear the loss of a friend with calmness, because he
comforts himself with the thought that he can have
another at any moment--then friendship is not worth
much. Moreover, if a wise man can help another by
communicating to him information and method, since no
wise man is omniscient, is not a wise man, if not in
possession of all knowledge, at least in possession of
all knowledge contributing to virtue and happiness? If
it be added, that what one learns from another he
learns by his own powers, and in consequence of
himself helping himself, does not this addition still
overlook the fact that the teacher’s activity is the
condition of the learner’s? True and beautiful as is
the language of Seneca: Friendship has its value in
itself alone; every wise man must wish to find those
like himself; the good have a natural love for the
good; the wise man needs a friend, not to have a nurse
in sickness and an assistant in trouble, but to have
some one whom he can tend and assist, and for whom he
can live and die--nevertheless, this language does not
meet the critical objection, that one who requires the
help of another, be it only to have an object for his
moral activity, cannot be wholly dependent on himself.
If friendship, according to a previously quoted
distinction, belongs to external goods, it makes man,
in a certain sense, dependent on externals. If its
essence is placed in an inward disposition of
friendliness, such a disposition depends on the
existence of those for whom it can be felt. Besides,
it involves the necessity of being reciprocated, and
of finding expression in outward conduct, to such an
extent that it is quite subversive of the absolute
independence of the individual.
Nor is the friendship of the wise the only form of
society which appeared to the Stoics necessary and
essential. If man is intended to associate with his
fellow-men in a society regulated by justice and law,
how can he withdraw from the most common
institution--the state? If virtue does not consist in
idle contemplation, but in action, how dare he lose
the opportunity of promoting good and repressing evil
by taking part in political life? If laws further the
well-being and security of the citizens, if they
advance virtue and happiness, how can the wise man
fail to regard them as beautiful and praiseworthy? For
the same reason, matrimony will command his respect.
He will neither deny himself a union so natural and
intimate, nor will he deprive the state of relays of
men nor society of the sight of well-ordered family
life Hence, in their writings and precepts, the Stoics
paid great attention to the state and to domestic
life. In marriage they required chastity and
moderation. Love was to be a matter of reason, not of
emotion--not a yielding to personal attractions, nor a
seeking sensual gratification. As to their views on
the constitution of a state, we know that they prefer
a mixed constitution, compounded of the three simple
forms, without objecting to other forms of government.
The wise man, according to Chrysippus, will not
despise the calling of a prince, if his interest so
require, and, if he cannot govern himself, will reside
at the court and in the camp of princes, particularly
of good princes.
The ideal of the Stoics, however, was not realized in
any one of the existing forms of government, but in
that polity of the wise which Zeno described,
undoubtedly when a Cynic, but which was fully set
forth by Chrysippus--a state without marriage, or
family, or temples, or courts, or public schools, or
coins--a state excluding no other states, because all
differences of nationality have been merged in a
common brotherhood of all men. Such an ideal may show
that, for the Stoic philosophers, there could be no
hearty sympathy with the state or the family, their
ideal state being, in truth, no longer a state.
Indeed, the whole tone of Stoicism, and still more,
the circumstances of the times to which it owed its
rise and growth, were against such a sympathy. If
Plato could find no place for a philosopher in the
political institutions of his time, how could a Stoic,
who looked for happiness more exclusively in seclusion
from the world, who contrasted, too, the wise man more
sharply with the multitude of fools, and lived for the
most part under political circumstances far less
favorable than Plato? To him the private life of a
philosopher must have seemed beyond compare more
attractive than a public career. An intelligent man,
taking advice from Chrysippus, avoids business; he
withdraws to peaceful retirement; and, though he may
consider it his duty not to stand aloof from public
life, still he can only actively take a part in it in
states which present an appreciable progress towards
perfection. But where could such states be found? Did
not Chrysippus state it as his conviction that a
statesman must either displease the Gods or displease
the people? And did not later Stoics accordingly
advise philosophers not to intermeddle at all in civil
matters? Labor for the commonwealth is only then a
duty when there is no obstacle to such labor; but, as
a matter of fact, there is always some obstacle, and
in particular, the condition of all existing states. A
philosopher who teaches and improves his fellow-men
benefits the state quite as much as a warrior, an
administrator, or a civil functionary.
Following out this idea, Epictetus dissuades from
matrimony and the begetting of children. Allowing that
the family relation may be admitted in a community of
wise men, he is of opinion that it is otherwise under
existing circumstances; for how can a true philosopher
engage in connections and actions which withdraw him
from the service of God? The last expression already
implies that unfavorable times were not the only cause
deterring the Stoics from caring for family or the
state, but that the occupation in itself seemed to
them a subordinate and limited one. This is stated in
plain terms by Seneca and Epictetus: He who feels
himself a citizen of the world finds in an individual
state a sphere far too limited, and prefers devoting
himself to the universe; man is no doubt intended to
be active, but the highest activity is intellectual
research. On the subject of civil society, opinions
were likely to vary, according to the peculiarities
and circumstances of individuals. The philosopher on
the throne was more likely than the freedman Epictetus
to feel himself a citizen of Rome as well as a citizen
of the world, and to lower the demands made on a
philosophic statesman. At the same time, the line
taken by the Stoic philosophy cannot be ignored. A
philosophy which attaches moral value to the
cultivation of intentions only, and considers all
external circumstances as indifferent, can hardly
produce a taste or a skill for overcoming those
outward interests and circumstances with which a
politician is chiefly concerned. A system which
regards the mass of men as fools, which denies to them
every healthy endeavor and all true knowledge, can
hardly bring itself unreservedly to work for a state,
the course and institutions of which depend upon the
majority of its members, and are planned with a view
to their needs, prejudices, and customs. Undoubtedly,
there were able statesmen among the Stoics of the
Roman period; but Rome, and not Stoicism, was the
cause of their statesmanship. Taken alone, Stoicism
could form excellent men, but hardly excellent
statesmen. And, looking to facts, not one of the old
masters of the School ever had or desired to have any
public office. Hence, when their opponents urged that
retirement was a violation of their principles, Seneca
could with justice meet the charge by replying, that
the true meaning of their principles ought to be
gathered from their actual conduct.
The positive substitute wherewith the Stoics thought
to replace the ordinary relations of civil society was
by a citizenship of the world. No preceding system had
been able to overcome the difficulty of nationalities.
Even Plato and Aristotle shared the prejudice of the
Greeks against foreigners. The Cynics alone appear as
the precursors of the Stoa, attaching slight value to
the citizenship of any particular state, in comparison
with citizenship of the world. With the Cynics, this
idea had not attained to the historical importance
which afterwards belonged to it; nor was it used so
much with a positive meaning, to express the essential
oneness of all mankind, as, in a negative sense, to
imply the philosopher’s independence of country and
home. From the Stoic philosophy it first received a
definite meaning, and was generally pressed into
service. The causes of this change may be sought, not
only in the historical surroundings amongst which
Stoicism grew up, but also in the person of its
founder. It was far easier for philosophy to overcome
national dislikes, after the genial Macedonian
conqueror had united the vigorous nationalities
comprised within his monarchy, not only under a
central government, but also in a common culture.
Hence the Stoic citizenship of the world may be
appealed to, to prove the assertion, that philosophic
Schools reflect the existing facts of history. On the
other hand, taking into account the bias given to a
philosopher’s teaching by his personal circumstances,
Zeno, being only half a Greek, would be more ready to
underestimate the distinction of Greek and barbarian
than any one of his predecessors.
However much these two causes--and, in particular, the
first--must have contributed to bring about the Stoic
ideal of a citizenship of the world, nevertheless the
connection of this idea with the whole of their system
is most obvious. If human society, as we have seen,
has for its basis the identity of reason in
individuals, what ground have we for limiting this
society to a single nation, or feeling ourselves more
nearly related to some men than to others? All men,
apart from what they have made themselves by their own
exertions, are equally near, since all equally
participate in reason. All are members of one body;
for one and the same nature has fashioned them all
from the same elements for the same destiny. Or, as
Epictetus expresses it in religious language, all men
are brethren, since all have in the same decree God
for their father. Man, therefore, who and whatever
else he may be, is the object of our solicitude,
simply as being man. No hostility and ill-treatment
should quench our benevolence. No one is so low but
that he has claims on the love and justice of his
fellow-men. Even the slave is a man deserving our
esteem, and able to claim from us his rights.
In their recognition of the universal rights of
mankind the Stoics did not go so far as to disapprove
of slavery. Attaching in general little value to
external circumstances, they cared the less to throw
down the gauntlet to the social institutions and
arrangements of their time. Still, they could not
wholly suppress a confession that slavery is unjust,
nor cease to aim at mitigating the evil both in theory
and practice. If all men are, as rational beings,
equal, all men together form one community. Reason is
the common law for all, and those who owe allegiance
to one law are members of one state. If the Stoics,
therefore, compared the world, in its more extended
sense, to a society, because of the connection of its
parts, they must, with far more reason, have allowed
that the world, in the narrower sense of the term,
including all rational beings, forms one community, to
which individual communities are related, as the
houses of a city are to the city collectively. Wise
men, at least, if not others, will esteem this great
community, to which all men belong, far above any
particular community in which the accident of birth
has placed them. They, at least, will direct their
efforts towards making all men feel themselves to be
citizens of one community; and, instead of framing
exclusive laws and constitutions, will try to live as
one family, under the common governance of reason. The
platform of social propriety receives hereby a
universal width. Man, by withdrawing from the outer
world into the recesses of his own intellectual and
moral state, becomes enabled to recognize everywhere
the same nature as his own, and to feel himself one
with the universe, by sharing with it the same nature
and the same destiny.
But, as yet, the moral problem is not exhausted.
Reason, the same as man's, rules pure and complete in
the universe; and if it is the business of man to give
play to reason in his own conduct, and to recognize it
in that of others, it is also his duty to subordinate
himself to collective reason, and to the course of the
world, over which it presides. In conclusion,
therefore, the relation of man to the course of the
world must be considered.
Firmly as the principles of the Stoic ethics insist
upon moral conduct, those ethics, judged by their
whole tone, cannot rest short of requiring an absolute
resignation to the course of the universe. This
requirement is based quite as much upon the historical
surroundings of their system as upon its intellectual
principles. How, in an age in which political freedom
was crushed by the oppression of the Macedonian and
subsequently of the Roman dominion, and the Roman
dominion was itself smothered under the despotism of
imperialism, in which Might, like a living fate,
crushed every attempt at independent action--how, in
such an age, could those aiming at higher objects than
mere personal gratification have any alternative but
to resign themselves placidly to the course of
circumstances which individuals and nations were alike
powerless to control? In making a dogma of fatalism.
Stoicism was only following the current of the age. At
the same time, as will be seen from what has been
said, it was only following the necessary consequences
of its own principles. All that is individual in the
world being only the result of a general connection of
cause and effect--only a carrying out of a universal
law--what remains possible, in the face of this
absolute necessity, but to yield unconditionally? How
can yielding be called a sacrifice, when the law to
which we yield is nothing less than the expression of
reason? Hence resignation to the world’s course was a
point chiefly insisted upon in the Stoic doctrine of
morality. The verses of Cleanthes, in which he submits
without reserve to the leading of destiny, are a theme
repeatedly worked out by the writers of this School.
The virtuous man, they say, will honor God by
resigning his will to the divine will; the divine will
he will think better than his own will; he will
remember that under all circumstances we must follow
destiny, but that it is the wise man’s prerogative to
follow of his own accord; that there is only one way
to happiness and independence--that of willing nothing
except what is in the nature of things, and what will
realize itself independently of our will.
Similar expressions are not wanting amongst other
philosophers. Nevertheless, by the Stoic philosophy,
the demand is pressed with particular force, and is
closely connected with its whole view of the world. In
resignation to destiny, the Stoic picture of the wise
man is completed. Therewith is included that peace and
happiness of mind, that gentleness and benevolence,
that discharge of all duties, and that harmony of
life, which together make up the Stoic definition of
virtue. Beginning by recognizing the existence of a
general law, morality ends by conditionally submitting
itself to the ordinances of that law.
The one case in which this resignation would give
place to active resistance to destiny is when man is
placed in circumstances calling for unworthy action or
endurance. Strictly speaking, the first case can never
arise, since, from the Stoic platform, no state of
life can be imagined which might not serve as an
occasion for virtuous conduct. It does, however, seem
possible that even the wise man may be placed by
fortune in positions which are for him unendurable;
and in this case he is allowed to withdraw from them
by suicide. The importance of this point in the Stoic
ethics will become manifest from the language of
Seneca, who asserts that the wise man’s independence
of externals depends, among other things, on his being
able to leave life at pleasure. To Seneca, the deed of
the younger Cato appears not only praiseworthy, but
the crowning act of success over destiny, the highest
triumph of the human will. By the chief teachers of
the Stoic School this doctrine was carried into
practice. Zeno, in old age, hung himself, because he
had broken his finger; Cleanthes, for a still less
cause, continued his abstinence till he died of
starvation, in order to traverse the whole way to
death; and, in later times, the example of Zeno and
Cleanthes was followed by Antipater.
In these cases suicide appears not only as a way of
escape, possible under circumstances, but absolutely
as the highest expression of moral freedom. Whilst all
are far from being advised to adopt this course,
everyone is required to embrace the opportunity of
dying with glory, when no higher duties bind him to
life. Everyone is urged, in case of need, to receive
death at his own hand, as a pledge of his
independence. Nor are cases of need decided by what
really makes a man unhappy--moral vice or folly. Vice
and folly must be met by other means. Death is no
deliverance from them, since it makes the bad no
better. The one satisfactory reason which the Stoics
recognized for taking leave of life is, when
circumstances over which we have no control make
continuance in life no longer desirable.
Such circumstances may be found in the greatest
variety of things. Cato committed suicide because of
the downfall of the republic; Zeno, because of a
slight injury received. According to Seneca, it is a
sufficient reason for committing suicide to anticipate
merely a considerable disturbance in our actions and
peace of mind. The infirmity of age, incurable
disease, a weakening of the powers of the mind, a
great degree of want, the tyranny of a despot from
which there is no escape, justify us--and even, under
circumstances, oblige us--to have recourse to this
remedy. Seneca, indeed, maintains that a philosopher
should never commit suicide in order to escape
suffering, but only to withdraw from restrictions in
following out the aim of life; but he is nevertheless
of opinion that anyone may rightly choose an easier
mode of death instead of a more painful one in
prospect, thus avoiding a freak of destiny and the
cruelty of man. Besides pain and sickness, Diogenes
also mentions a case in which suicide becomes a duty,
for the sake of others. According to another
authority, five cases are enumerated by the Stoics in
which it is allowed to put oneself to death; if, by so
doing, a real service can be rendered to others, as in
the case of sacrificing oneself for one's country; to
avoid being compelled to do an unlawful action;
otherwise, on the ground of poverty, chronic illness,
or incipient weakness of mind.
In nearly all these cases, the things referred to
belong to the class of things which were reckoned as
indifferent by the Stoics; and hence arises the
apparent paradox, with which their opponents
immediately twitted them, that not absolute and moral
evils, but only outward circumstances, are admitted as
justifying suicide. The paradox, however, loses its
point when it is remembered that, to the Stoics, life
and death are quite as much indifferent as all other
external things. To them, nothing really good appears
to be involved in the question of suicide, but a
choice between two things morally indifferent--one of
which, life, is only preferable to the other, death,
whilst the essential conditions for a life according
to nature are satisfied. The philosopher, therefore,
says Seneca, chooses his mode of death just as he
chooses a ship for a journey or a house to live in. He
leaves life as he would leave a banquet--when it is
time. He lays aside his body when it no longer suits
him, as he would lay aside worn-out clothes; and
withdraws from life as he would withdraw from a house
no longer weather-proof.
A very different question, however, it is, whether
life can be treated in this way as something
indifferent, and whether it is consistent with an
unconditional resignation to the course of the world,
to evade by personal interposition what destiny with
its unalterable laws has decreed for us. Stoicism may,
indeed, allow this course of action. But in so doing
does it not betray its ill-success in the attempt to
combine, without contradiction, two main tendencies so
different as that of individual independence and that
of submission to the universe?
Chapter XIII. The Relation of the Stoic Philosophy
to Religion.
IT would be impossible to give a full account
of the philosophy of the Stoics without treating of
their theology; for no early system is so closely
connected with religion as that of the Stoics. Founded
as is their whole view of the world upon the idea of
one Divine Being, begetting from Himself and
containing in Himself all finite creatures, upholding
them by His might, ruling them according to an
unalterable law, and thus manifesting Himself
everywhere, their philosophy bears a decidedly
religious character. Indeed, there is hardly a single
prominent feature in the Stoic system which is not,
more or less, connected with theology. A very
considerable portion of that system, moreover,
consists of strictly theological questions; such as
arguments for the existence of deity, and for the rule
of Providence; investigations into the nature of God,
His government, and presence in the world; the
relation of human activity to the divine ordinances;
and all the various questions connected with the terms
freedom and necessity. The natural science of the
Stoics begins by evolving things from God; it ends
with resolving them again into God. God is thus the
beginning and end of the world’s development. In like
manner, their moral philosophy begins with the notion
of divine law, which, in the form of eternal reason,
controls the actions of men; and ends by requiring
submission to the will of God, and resignation to the
course of the universe. A religious sanction is thus
given to all moral duties. All virtuous actions are a
fulfillment of the divine will and the divine law.
That citizenship of the world, in particular, which
constitutes the highest point in the Stoic morality,
is connected with the notion of a common relationship
of all men to God. Again, that inward repose of the
philosopher, those feelings of freedom and
independence, on which so much stress is laid, rest
principally on the conviction that man is related to
God. In a word, Stoicism is not only a system of
philosophy, but also a system of religion. As such it
was regarded by its first adherents, witness the
fragments of Cleanthes; and as such it afforded, in
later times, together with Platonism, to the best and
most cultivated men, wherever the influence of Greek
culture extended a substitute for declining natural
religion, a satisfaction for religions cravings, and a
support for moral life.
This philosophic religion is quite independent of the
traditional religion. The Stoic philosophy contains no
feature of importance which we can pronounce with
certainty to be taken from the popular faith. The true
worship of God, according to their view, consists only
in the mental effort to know God, and in a moral and
pious life. A really acceptable prayer can have no
reference to external goods; it can only have for its
object a virtuous and devout mind. Still, there were
reasons which led the Stoics to seek a closer union
with the popular faith. A system which attached so
great an importance to popular opinion, particularly
in proving the existence of God, could not, without
extreme danger to itself, declare the current opinions
respecting the Gods to be erroneous. And again, the
ethical platform of the Stoic philosophy imposed on
its adherents the duty of upholding rather than
overthrowing the popular creed--that creed forming a
barrier against the violence of human passions. The
practical value of the popular faith may, then, be the
cause of their theological orthodoxy. Just as the
Romans, long after all faith in the Gods had been lost
under the influence of Greek culture, still found it
useful and necessary to uphold the traditional faith,
so the Stoics may have feared that, were the worship
of the people’s Gods to be suspended, that respect for
God and the divine law on which they depended for the
support of their own moral tenets would at the same
time be exterminated.
Meantime, they did not deny that much in the popular
belief would not harmonize with their principles; and
that both the customary forms of religious worship,
and also the mythical representations of the Gods,
were altogether untenable. So little did they conceal
their strictures, that it is clear that conviction,
and not fear (there being no longer occasion for
fear), was the cause of their leaning towards
tradition. Zeno spoke with contempt of the erection of
sacred edifices; for how can a thing be sacred which
is erected by builders and laborers? Seneca denies the
good of prayer. He considers it absurd to entertain
fear for the Gods, who are ever-beneficent beings.
God he would have worshipped, not by sacrifices and
ceremonies, but by purity of life; not in temples of
stone, but in the shrine of the heart. Of images of
the Gods, and the devotion paid to them, he speaks
with strong disapprobation; of the unworthy fables of
mythology, with bitter ridicule; and he calls the
popular Gods, without reserve, creations of
superstition, whom the philosopher only invokes
because it is the custom so to do. Moreover, the Stoic
in Cicero, and the elder authorities quoted by him,
allow that the popular beliefs and the songs of the
poets are full of superstition and foolish legends.
Chrysippus is expressly said to have declared the
distinction of sex among the Gods, and other features
in which they resemble men, to be childish fancies;
seasons called Gods, as was done by Zeno, or at least
by bis School. Yet, it must be remembered, that the
Stoics referred these times and seasons to heavenly
bodies, as their material embodiments.
As the stars are the first manifestation, so the
elements are the first particular forms of the Divine
Being, and the most common materials for the exercise
of the divine powers. It is, however, becoming that
the all-pervading divine mind should not only be
honored in its primary state, but likewise in its
various derivate forms, as air, water, earth, and
elementary fire.
All other things, too, which, by their utility to man,
display in a high degree the beneficent power of God,
appeared to the Stoics to deserve divine honors, such
honors not being paid to the things themselves, but to
the powers active within them. They did not,
therefore, hesitate to give the names of Gods to
fruits and wine, and other gifts of the Gods.
How, then, could they escape the inference that among
other beneficent beings, the heroes of antiquity in
particular deserve religious honors, seeing that in
these benefactors of mankind, whom legend
commemorates, the Divine Spirit did not show Himself
under the lower form of a stable disposition, as in
the elements, nor yet as simple nature, as in plants,
but as a rational soul? Such deified men had,
according to the Stoic view--which, on this point,
agrees with the well-known theory of Euemerus--greatly
helped to swell the number of the popular Gods; nor
had the Stoics themselves any objection to their
worship. Add to this the personification of human
qualities and states of mind, and it will be seen what
ample opportunity the Stoics had for recognizing
everywhere in nature and in the world of man divine
agencies and powers, and, consequently, Gods in the
wider sense of the term. When once it is allowed that
the name of God may be diverted from the Being to whom
it properly belongs and applied, in a derivative
sense, to what is impersonal and a mere manifestation
of divine power, the door is opened to everything;
and, with such concessions, the Stoic system could
graft into itself even exceptional forms of
polytheism.
With the worship of heroes is also connected the
doctrine of demons. The soul, according to the Stoic
view already set forth, is of divine origin, a part of
and emanation from God. Or, distinguishing more
accurately in the soul one part from the rest,
divinity belongs to reason only, as the governing
part. Now, since reason alone protects man from evil
and conducts him to happiness--this, too, was the
popular belief--reason may be described as the
guardian spirit, or demon, in man. Not only by the
younger members of the Stoic School, by Posidonius,
Seneca, Epictetus, and Antoninus, are the popular
notions of demons, as by Plato aforetime, explained in
this sense, but the same method is pursued by
Chrysippus. who made eudaimonia, or happiness, consist
in a harmony of the demon in man (which, in this case,
can only be his own will and understanding) with the
will of God. Little were the Stoics aware that, by
such explanations, they were attributing to popular
notions a meaning wholly foreign to them. But it does
not therefore follow that they shared the popular
belief in guardian spirits. Their system, however,
left room for believing that, besides the human soul
and the spirits of the stars, other rational souls
might exist, having a definite work to perform in the
world, subject to the law of general necessity, and
knit into the chain of cause and effect. Nay, more,
such beings might seem to them necessary for the
completeness of the universe. What reason have we,
then, to express doubt, when we are told that the
Stoics believed in the existence of demons, playing a
part in man and caring for him? Is there anything
extraordinary, from the Stoic platform, in holding
that some of these demons are by nature inclined to do
harm, and that these tormentors are used by the deity
for the punishment of the wicked, especially when in
such a strict system of necessity these demons could
only work, like the powers of nature, conformably with
the laws of the universe and without disturbing those
laws, occupying the same ground as lightning,
earthquakes, and drought? And yet the language of
Chrysippus, when speaking of evil demons who neglect
the duties entrusted to them, sounds as though it were
only figurative and tentative language, not really
meant. Besides, the later Stoics made themselves merry
over the Jewish and Christian notions of demons and
demoniacal possession.
Even without accepting demons, there were not wanting
in the Stoic system points with which the popular
beliefs could be connected, if it was necessary to
find in these beliefs some deeper meaning. It mattered
not that these beliefs were often so distorted in the
process of accommodation as to be no longer recognized
The process required a regular code of interpretation
by means of which a philosophic mind could see its own
thoughts in the utterances of commonplace thinkers. By
the Stoics, as by their Jewish and Christian
followers, this code of interpretation was found in
the method of allegorical interpretation--a method
which received a most extended application, in order
to bridge over the gulf between the older and the more
modern types of culture. Zeno, and still more
Cleanthes, Chrysippus, and their successors, sought to
discover natural principles and moral ideas--the
physical aspects,--in the Gods of popular belief and
the stories of these Gods, and supposed that such
principles and ideas were represented in these stories
in a sensuous form. In this attempt, they clung to the
poems of Homer and Hesiod, the Bible of the Greeks,
without, however, excluding other mythology from the
sphere of their investigation. One chief instrument
which they, and modern lovers of the symbolical
following in their footsteps, employed was a
capricious playing with etymologies of which so many
instances are on record. Like most allegorisers, they
also laid down certain principles of interpretation
sensible enough theoretically, but proving, by the use
which was made of them, that their scientific
appearance was only a blind to conceal the most
capricious vagaries. Approaching in some of their
explanations to the original bases of mythological
formation, they were still unable to shake off the
curious notion that the originators of myths, fully
conscious of all their latent meanings, had framed
them as pictures to appeal to the senses; and, in
innumerable cases, they resorted to explanations so
entirely without foundation that they would have been
impossible to anyone possessing a sound view of nature
and the origin of legends. To make theory tally with
practice, the founder of the School--following
Antisthenes, and setting an example afterwards
repeated by both Jews and Christians--maintained that
Homer only in some places expressed himself according
to truth, in others according to popular opinion. Thus
did Stoicism surround itself with the necessary
instruments for the most extended allegorical and
dogmatic interpretation.
Proceeding further to inquire how this method was
applied to particular stories, the first point which
attracts attention is the contrast which they draw
between Zeus and the remaining Gods. From their belief
in one divine principle everywhere at work, it
followed as a corollary that this contrast, which
elsewhere in Greek mythology is only a difference of
degree, was raised to a specific and absolute
difference. Zeus was compared to other Gods as an
incorruptible God to transitory divine beings. To the
Stoics, as to their predecessor Heraclitus. Zeus is
the one primary Being, who has engendered, and again
absorbs into himself, all things and all Gods. He is
the universe as a unity, the primary fire, the ether,
the spirit of the world, the universal reason, the
general law or destiny. All other Gods, as being parts
of the world, are only parts and manifestations of
Zeus--only special names of the one God who has many
names. That part of Zeus which goes over into air is
called Hera; and its lower strata, full of vapors,
Hades; that which becomes elementary fire is called
Hephaestus; that which becomes water, Poseidon; that
which becomes earth, Demeter, Hestia, and Rhea;
lastly, that portion which remains in the upper region
is called Athene in the more restricted sense. And
since, according to the Stoics, the finer elements are
the same as spirit, Zeus is not only the soul of the
universe, but Athene, Reason, Intelligence,
Providence. The same Zeus appears in other respects as
Hermes, Dionysus, Hercules. The Homeric story of the
binding and liberation of Zeus points to the truth,
already established in Providence, that the order of
the world rests on the balance of the elements. The
rise and succession of the elements is symbolized in
the hanging of Hera; the arrangement of the spheres of
the universe, in the golden chain by which the
Olympians thought to pull down Zeus. The lameness of
Hephaestus goes partly to prove the difference of the
earthly from the heavenly fire, and partly implies
that earthly fire can as little do without wood as the
lame can do without a wooden support; and if, in
Homer, Hephaestus is hurled down from heaven, the
meaning of the story is, that in ancient times men
lighted their fires by lightning from heaven and the
rays of the sun. The connection of Hera with Zeus
points to the relation of the ether to the air
surrounding it; and the well-known occurrence on
Mount Ida was referred to the same event. The still
more offensive scene in the Samian picture was
expounded by Chrysippus as meaning that the
fertilizing powers of God are brought to bear upon
matter. A similar meaning is found by Heraclitus in
the story of Proteus, and in that of the shield of
Achilles. If Hephaestus intended this shield to be a
representation of this world, what else is thereby
meant but that, by the influence of primary fire,
matter has been shaped into a world?
In a similar way, the Homeric theomachy was explained
by many to mean a conjunction of the seven planets,
which would involve the world in great trouble.
Heraclitus, however, gives the preference to an
interpretation, half physical and half moral, which
may have been already advanced by Cleanthes. Ares and
Aphrodite, rashness and profligacy, are opposed by
Athene, or prudence; Leto, forgetfulness, is attacked
by Hermes, the revealing word: Apollo, the sun, by
Poseidon, the God of the water, with whom, however, he
comes to terms, because the sun is fed by the vapors
of the water; Artemis, the moon, is opposed by Hera,
the air, through which it passes, and which often
obscures it; Fluvius, or earthly water, by Hephaestus,
or earthly fire. That Apollo is the sun, and Artemis
the moon, no one doubts; nor did it cause any
difficulty to these mythologists to find the moon also
in Athene. Many subtle discussions were set on foot by
the Stoics respecting the name, the form, and the
attributes of these Gods, particularly by Cleanthes,
for whom the sun had particular importance, as being
the seat of the power which rules the world. The
stories of the birth of the Lotoides and the defeat of
the dragon Pytho are, according to Antipater,
symbolical of events which took place at the formation
of the world, and the creation of the sun and moon.
Others find in the descent of two Gods from Leto the
simpler thought, that sun and moon came forth out of
darkness. In the same spirit, Heraclitus, without
disparaging the original meaning of the story, sees in
the swift-slaying arrows of Apollo a picture of
devastating pestilence; but then, in an extraordinary
manner, misses the natural sense, in gathering from
the Homeric story of Apollo’s reconciliation (II. i.
53) the lesson, that Achilles stayed the plague by the
medical science which Chiron had taught him.
Far more plausible is the explanation given of the
dialogue of Athene with Achilles, and of Hermes with
Ulysses. These dialogues are stated to be simply
soliloquies of the two heroes respectively. But the
Stoic skill in interpretation appears in its fullest
glory in supplying the etymological meanings of the
various names and epithets which are attributed to
Athene. We learn, for instance, that the name
Tritogeneia refers to the three divisions of
philosophy. Heraclitus discovers the same divisions in
the three heads of Cerberus. Chrysippus, in a diffuse
manner, proves that the coming forth of the Goddess
from the head of Zens is not at variance with his view
of the seat of reason. It has been already observed
that Dionysus means wine, and Demeter fruit; but, just
as the latter was taken to represent the earth and its
nutritions powers, so Dionysus was further supposed to
stand for the principle of natural life, the
productive and sustaining breath of life; and since
this breath comes from the sun, according to
Cleanthes, it was not difficult to find the sun
represented by the God of wine. Moreover, the stories
of the birth of Dionysus, his being torn to pieces by
Titans, his followers, no less than the rape of
Proserpine, and the institution of agriculture, and
the names of the respective Gods, afforded ample
material for the interpreting tastes of the Stoics.
The Fates, as their name already indicates, stand for
the righteous and invariable rule of destiny; the
Graces, as to whose names, number, and qualities
Chrysippus has given the fullest discussion, represent
the virtues of benevolence and gratitude; the Muses,
the divine origin of culture. Ares is war; Aphrodite
unrestrained passion, or, more generally, absence of
control. Other interpreters, and among them
Empedocles, consider Ares to represent the separating,
Aphrodite the uniting, power of nature. The stories of
the two deities being wounded by Diomedes, of their
adulterous intrigues, and their being bound by
Hephaestus, are explained in various ways--morally,
physically, technically, and historically.
In the case of another God, Pan, the idea of the
Allnear was suggested simply by the name. His shaggy
goat's feet were taken to represent the solid earth,
and the human form of his upper limbs implied that the
sovereign power in the world resides above. To the
Stoic without a misgiving as to these and similar
explanations, it was a matter of small difficulty to
make the Titan Iapetus stand for language, and Coeus
for quality. Add to this the many more or less
ingenious explanations of the well-known stories of
Uranos and Cronos, and we are still far from having
exhausted the resources of the Stoic explanations of
mythology. The most important attempts of this kind
have, however, been sufficiently noticed.
Besides the legends of the Gods, the legends of the
heroes attracted considerable attention in the
Stoic-Schools. Specially were the persons of Hercules
and Ulysses singled out for the sake of illustrating
the ideal of the wise man. But here, too, various
modes of interpretation meet and cross. According to
Cornutus, the God Hercules must be distinguished from
the hero of the same name--the God being nothing less
than Reason, ruling in the world without a superior:
and the grammarian makes every effort to unlock with
this key his history and attributes. Nevertheless,
with all his respect for Cleanthes, he could not
accept that Stoic's explanation of the twelve labors
of Hercules. Heraclitus has probably preserved the
chief points in this explanation. Hercules is a
teacher of mankind, initiated into the heavenly
wisdom. He overcomes the wild boar, the lion, and the
bull, i.e. the lusts and passions of men; he drives
away the deer, i.e. cowardice; he purifies the stall
of Augeas from filth, i.e. he purifies the life of men
from extravagances; he frightens away the birds, i.e.
empty hopes; and burns to ashes the many-headed hydra
of pleasure. He brings the keeper of the nether world
to light, with his three heads--these heads
representing the three chief divisions of philosophy.
In the same way, the wounding of Hera and Hades by
Hercules is explained. Hera, the Goddess of the air,
represents the fog of ignorance, the three-barbed
arrow undeniably (so thought the Stoics) pointing to
philosophy, with its threefold division, in its
heavenly flight. The laying prostrate of Hades by that
arrow implies that philosophy has access even to
things most secret. The Odyssey is explained by
Heraclitus in the same strain, nor was he apparently
the first so to do. In Ulysses you behold a pattern of
all virtues, and an enemy of all vices. He flees from
the country of the Lotophagi, i.e. from wicked
pleasures; he stays the wild rage of the Cyclopes; he
calms the winds, having first secured a prosperous
passage by his knowledge of the stars; the attractions
of pleasure in the house of Circe he overcomes,
penetrates into the secrets of Hades, learns from the
Sirens the history of all times, saves himself from
the Charybdis of profligacy and the Scylla of
shamelessness, and, in abstaining from the oxen of the
sun, overcomes sensuous desires. Such explanations may
suffice to show how the whole burden of the myths was
resolved into allegory by the Stoics, how little they
were conscious of foisting in foreign elements, and
how they degraded to mere symbols of philosophical
ideas those very heroes on whose real existence they
continually insisted.
The Stoic theology has engaged a good deal of our
attention, not only because it is instructive to
compare their views, in general and in detail, with
similar views advanced nowadays, but also because it
forms a very characteristic and important part of
their entire system. To us, much of it appears to be a
mere worthless trilling; but, to the Stoics, these
explanations were solemnly earnest. To them they
seemed to be the only means of rescuing the people’s
faith, of meeting the severe charges brought against
tradition and the works of the poets, on which a Greek
had been fed from infancy. Unable to break entirely
with these traditions, they still would not sacrifice
to them their scientific and moral convictions. Can
we, then, wonder that they attempted the impossible,
and sought to unite contradictions? or that such an
attempt landed them in forced and artificial methods
of interpretation?
Illustrative of the attitude of the Stoics towards
positive religion are their views on divination. The
importance attached by them to the prophetic art
appears in the diligence which the chiefs of this
School devoted to discussing it. The ground for the
later teaching having been prepared by Zeno and
Cleanthes, Chrysippus gave the finishing touch to the
Stoic dogmas on the subject. Particular treatises
respecting divination were drawn up by Sphaerus,
Diogenes, Antipater, and, last of all, by Posidonius.
The subject was also fully treated by Boethius, and by
Panaetius from a somewhat different side. The common
notions as to prognostics and oracles could not
commend themselves to these philosophers, nor could
they approve of common soothsaying. In a system so
purely based on nature as theirs, the supposition that
God works for definite ends after the manner of men,
exceptionally announcing to one or the other a
definite result--in short, the marvelous--was out of
place. But to infer thence--as their opponents, the
Epicureans, did--that the whole art of divination is a
delusion, was more than the Stoics could do. The
belief in an extraordinary care of God for individual
men was too comforting an idea for them to renounce;
they not only appealed to divination as the strongest
proof of the existence of Gods and the government of
Providence, but they also drew the converse
conclusion, that, if there be Gods, there must also be
divination, since the benevolence of the Gods would
not allow them to refuse to mankind so inestimable a
gift. The conception of destiny, too, and the nature
of man, appeared to Posidonius to lead to the belief
in divination; if all that happens is the outcome of
an unbroken chain of cause and effect, there must be
signs indicating the existence of causes, from which
certain effects result; and if the soul of man is in
its nature divine, it must also possess the capacity,
under circumstances, of observing what generally
escapes its notice. Lest, however, the certainty of
their belief should suffer from lacking the support of
experience, the Stoics had collected a number of
instances of verified prophecies; but with so little
discrimination, that we should only wonder at their
credulity, did we not know the low state of historical
criticism in their time, and the readiness with which,
in all ages, men believe whatever agrees with their
prejudices.
In what way, then, can the two facts be combined--the
belief in prophecy, on the one hand, and, on the
other, the denial of unearthly omens arising from an
immediate divine influence? In answering this
question, the Stoics adopted the only course which
their system allowed. The marvelous, which, as such,
they could not admit, was referred to natural laws,
from which it was speculatively deduced. The admirable
Panaetius is the only Stoic who is reported to have
maintained the independence of his judgment by denying
omens, prophecy, and astrology. Just as in modern
times Leibniz and so many others both before and after
him thought to purge away from the marvelous all that
is accidental and superhuman, and to find in wonders
links in the general chain of natural causes, so, too,
the Stoics, by assuming a natural connection between
the token and its fulfillment, made an effort to
rescue omens and divination, and to explain portents
as the natural symptoms of certain occurrences. Nor
did they confine themselves to cases in which the
connection between the prophecy and the event can be
proved. They insisted upon divination in cases in
which it cannot possibly be verified. The flight of
birds and the entrails of victims are stated to be
natural indications of coming events; and there is
said to be even a formal connection between the
positions of the stars and the individuals born under
those positions. If it is urged, that in this case
omens must be far more numerous than they are supposed
to be, the Stoics answered, that omens are countless,
but that only the meaning of a few is known to men. If
the question is asked, how is it that, in public
sacrifices, the priest should always offer those very
animals whose entrails contain omens, Chrysippus and
his followers did not hesitate to affirm that the same
sympathy which exists between objects and omens also
guides the sacrificer in the choice of a victim. And
yet so bald was this hypothesis, that they had. at the
same time, a second answer in reserve, viz. that the
corresponding change in the entrails did not take
place until the victim had been chosen. In support of
such views, their only appeal was to the almighty
power of God; but, in making this appeal, the
deduction of omens from natural causes was at an end.
The Stoics could not altogether suppress a suspicion
that an unchangeable predestination of all events has
rendered individual activity superfluous, nor meet the
objection that, on the hypothesis of necessity,
divination itself is unnecessary. They quieted
themselves, however, with the thought that divination,
and the actions resulting from divination, are
included among the causes foreordained by destiny.
Divination, or soothsaying, consists in the capacity
to read and interpret omens; and this capacity is,
according to the Stoics, partly a natural gift, and
partly acquired by art and study. The natural gift of
prophecy is based, as other philosophers had already
laid down, on the relationship of the human soul to
God. Sometimes it manifests itself in sleep, at other
times in ecstasy. A taste for higher revelations will
be developed, in proportion as the soul is withdrawn
from the world of sense, and from all thought
respecting things external. The actual cause of the
prophetic gift was referred to influences coming to
the soul partly from God or the universal spirit
diffused throughout the world, and partly from the
souls which haunt the air or demons. External causes,
however, contribute to put people in a state of
enthusiasm.
Artificial prophesying, or the art of foretelling the
future, depends upon observation and guess-work. One
who could survey all causes in their effects on one
another would need no observation. Such a one would be
able to deduce the whole series of events from the
given causes. But God alone is able to do this. Hence
men must gather the knowledge of future events from
the indications by which their coming is announced.
These indications may be of every variety; and hence
all possible forms of foretelling the future were
allowed by the Stoics; the inspection of entrails,
divination by lightning and other natural phenomena,
by the flight of birds, and omens of every kind. Some
idea of the mass of superstition which the Stoics
admitted and encouraged may be gathered from the first
book of Cicero’s treatise on divination. The
explanation of these omens being, however, a matter of
skill, individuals in this, as in every other art, may
often go wrong in their interpretation. To make sure
against mistakes tradition is partly of use, since it
establishes by manifold experiences the meaning of
each omen; and the moral state of the prophet is quite
as important for scientifically foretelling the future
as for the natural gift of divination. Purity of heart
is one of the most essential conditions of prophetic
success.
In all these questions the moral character of Stoic
piety is ever to the fore, and great pains were taken
by the Stoics to bring their belief in prophecy into
harmony with their philosophic view of the world.
Nevertheless, it is clear that success could not be
theirs either in making this attempt, or indeed in
dealing with any other parts of the popular belief.
Struggling with indefatigable zeal in an attempt so
hopeless, they proved at least the sincerity of their
wish to reconcile religion and philosophy; but they
also disclosed by these endeavors a misgiving that
science, which had put on so bold a face, was not in
itself sufficient, but needed support from the
traditions of religion, and from a belief in divine
revelations. Probably we shall not be far wrong in
referring to this practical need the seeming vagaries
of men like Chrysippus, who, with the clearest
intellectual powers, could be blind to the folly of
the methods they adopted in defending untenable and
antiquated opinions. These vagaries show in Stoicism
practical interests preponderating over science. They
also establish the connection of Stoicism with Schools
which doubted altogether the truth of the
understanding, and thought to supplement it by divine
revelations. Thus the Stoic theory of divination leads
directly to the Neopythagorean and Neoplatonic
doctrine of revelation.
Chapter XIV. The Stoic Philosophy as a Whole and
Its Historical Position.
HAVING now investigated the Stoic system in
detail, we are in a position to pass a definite
judgment on the scope of the Stoic philosophy, the
import and the relation of its various parts, and its
historical position. Its peculiar character manifests
itself before all things in the three points, to which
attention was drawn at the outset:--its pre-eminently
practical tone, the determination of this practical
tendency by the notions of the good and of virtue, and
the use of logic and natural science as a scientific
basis. Speculative knowledge is not, as we have seen,
to the Stoics an end in itself, but only a means for
producing a right moral attitude; all philosophical
research stands directly or indirectly in the service
of virtue. Both in the earlier and in the later days
of its existence the Stoic School advocated this
principle in the most determined and exclusive manner,
nor was it even denied by Chrysippus, the chief
representative of its science and learning.
If it be then asked what is the right moral attitude,
the Stoics reply: action conformable to nature and
reason--in other words, virtue. Virtue, however,
implies two things. On the one hand it implies the
resignation of the individual to the universe,
obedience to the universal law; on the other hand it
implies the harmony of man with himself, the dominion
of the higher over the lower nature, of reason over
emotion, and the rising superior to everything which
does not belong to his true nature. Both statements
may be reconciled, because the law of morality is
addressed only to reasonable beings, and is the law of
their nature, and can only be carried into execution
by their own exertions. Still, in the Stoic ethics,
two currents of thought may be clearly distinguished,
which from time to time come into actual collision;
the one requiring the individual to live for the
common good and for society, the other impelling him
to live for himself only, to emancipate himself from
all that is not himself, and to console himself with
the feeling of virtue. The first of these tendencies
impels man to seek the society of others; the second
enables him to dispense with it. From the former
spring the virtues of justice, sociability, love of
man; from the latter, the inner freedom and happiness
of the virtuous man. The former culminates in
citizenship of the world; the latter in the
self-sufficingness of the wise man. In as far as
virtue includes everything that can be required of
man, happiness depends on it alone; nothing is good
but virtue, nothing is evil but vice; all that is not
connected with the moral nature is indifferent. On the
other hand, in as far as virtue is based on human
nature, it stands on the same footing with all else
that is conformable with nature. If its own peculiar
value cannot be surrendered, no more can it be
required that we should be indifferent to its
conformity to nature, that it should not have for us
some positive or negative value, or in some way affect
our feelings. Therewith the doctrine of things
indifferent and the wise man’s freedom from emotions
begins to totter. Lastly, if we look at the way in
which virtue exists in man, we arrive at different
results, according as we look at its essence or its
manifestation. Virtue consists in acting conformably
with reason, and reason is one and undivided; hence it
appears that virtue forms an undivided unity, and must
be possessed whole and entire or not at all. From this
proposition the contrast of the wise and foolish man,
with all its bluntness and extravagances, is only a
legitimate consequence. Or, again, if we look at the
conditions upon which, owing to human nature, the
acquisition and possession of virtue depends, the
conviction is inevitable that the wise man as drawn by
the Stoics never occurs in reality. Hence the
conclusion is undeniable that the contrast between
wise men and fools is more uncertain than it at first
appeared to be. Thus all the main features of the
Stoic ethics may be simply deduced from their one
fundamental notion, that rational action or virtue is
the only good.
Not only does this view of ethics require a peculiar
theory of the world to serve as its scientific basis,
but it has a reflex action also, influencing alike the
tone and the results of theoretic inquiry. If the duty
of man is declared to consist in bringing his actions
into harmony with the laws of the universe, it becomes
also necessary that he should endeavor himself to know
the world and its laws. The more his knowledge of the
world increases, the greater will be the value which
he attaches to the forms of scientific procedure. If,
moreover, man is required to be nothing more than an
instrument of the universal law, it is only consistent
to suppose an absolute regularity of procedure in the
universe, an unbroken connection of cause and effect,
and ultimately to refer everything to one highest
all-moving cause, and to include everything under one
primary substance. If in human life the individual has
no rights as against the laws of the universe, then
all that is of individual occurrence in the world is
powerless against universal necessity. On the other
hand, if in the case of man everything turns upon
strength of will, then likewise in the universe the
acting power must be regarded as the highest and most
exalted. There arises thus that view of the world as a
series of forces which constitutes one of the most
peculiar and thorough-going characteristics of the
Stoic view of nature. Lastly, if such excessive
importance is attached to practical conduct as is done
by the Stoics, that sensuous view of the world which
finds its crudest expression in the Stoic Materialism
and reliance on the senses, will most nearly accord
with speculation, a union of ethical and speculative
elements, in which both were more definitely
determined by one another; still the ethical platform
is the one on which its formation commences, and which
primarily determined its course and results.
In order to obtain a more accurate notion of the rise
of Stoicism, the premises on which it proceeds, and
the grounds on which it is based, we must take a
glance at its relation to preceding systems. The
Stoics themselves deduced their philosophical pedigree
directly from Antisthenes, and indirectly from
Socrates. Clear as is their connection with both these
philosophers, it would nevertheless be a mistake to
regard their teaching as a revival of Cynicism, still
more to regard it as a simple following of Socrates.
From both it undoubtedly borrowed much. The
self-sufficiency of virtue, the distinction of things
good, evil, and indifferent, the ideal picture of the
wise man, the whole withdrawal from the outer world
within the precincts of the mind, and the strength of
moral will, are ideas taken from the Cynics. In the
spirit of Cynicism, too, it explained general ideas as
simply names. Not to mention many peculiarities of
ethics, the contrasting of one God with the many
popular Gods, and the allegorical explanation of
myths, were likewise points borrowed from Cynicism.
The identification of virtue with intelligence, the
belief that virtue was one, and could be imparted by
teaching, were at once in the spirit of Socrates and
also in that of the Cynics. The argument for the
existence of God based on the subordination of means
to ends, the whole view of the world as a system of
means and ends, and the Stoic theory of Providence,
are views peculiarly Socratic; and the Stoics followed
Socrates in ethics by identifying the good and the
useful.
And yet the greatness of the interval which separates
the Stoics even from the Cynics becomes at once
apparent on considering the relation of Aristo to the
rest of the Stoic School. In refusing to meddle with
natural or mental science, or even with ethical
considerations at all, Aristo faithfully reflects the
principles of Antisthenes. In asserting the unity of
virtue to such an extent that all virtues are merged
in one, he was only repeating similar expressions of
Antisthenes. In denying any difference in value to
things morally indifferent, and in placing the highest
morality in this indifference, he was, according to
the older writers, reasserting a Cynic tenet.
Conversely in denying these statements, as the great
majority of Stoics did, the points are indicated in
which Stoicism differed from Cynicism. In the feeling
of moral independence, and in invincible strength of
will, the Cynic is opposed to the whole world; he
needs for virtue no scientific knowledge of the world
and its laws; he regards nothing external to himself;
he allows nothing to influence his conduct, and
attaches value to nothing; but, in consequence, he
remains with his virtue confined to himself; virtue
makes him independent of men and circumstances, but it
has neither the will nor the power to interpose
effectively in the affairs of life, and to infuse
therein new moral notions. Stoicism insists upon the
self-sufficiency of virtue quite as strongly as
Cynicism, and will allow quite as little that anything
except virtue can be a good in the strictest sense of
the term. But in Stoicism the individual is not nearly
so sharply opposed to the outer world as in Cynicism.
The Stoic is too cultivated; he knows too well that he
is a part of the universe to ignore the value of an
intellectual view of the world, or to neglect the
natural conditions of moral action, as things of no
moment. What he aims at is not only a
negation--independence from externals--but a positive
position--life according to nature; and that life only
he considers according to nature which is in harmony
with the laws of the universe as well as with those of
human nature. Hence Stoicism is not only far in
advance of Cynicism by its intellectual attitude, but
its moral philosophy also breathes a freer and milder
spirit. Let only the principles of the Stoics on the
necessity and value of scientific knowledge be
compared with the sophistical assertions of
Antisthenes, destructive of all knowledge; or the
cultivated logical form of the intellectual edifice of
the Stoics, with the chaotic condition of Cynic
thought; or the careful metaphysical and psychological
researches and the copious learning of the School of
Chrysippus, with the Cynics’ contempt for all theory
and all learned research, and it becomes apparent at
once how deep-seated is the difference between the
two systems, and how little Stoicism as a philosophic
system can be deduced from Cynicism.
In ethics, too, the difference of the two Schools is
also fully apparent. Stoic morality recognizes, at
least conditionally, a positive and negative value in
external things and circumstances; the Cynic allows to
these absolutely no value. The former forbids
affection contrary to reason, the latter any and every
kind of affection. The former throws the individual
back upon human society, the latter isolates him. The
former teaches citizenship of the world in a positive
sense, requiring all to feel themselves one with their
fellow-men; the latter in a negative sense, that of
feeling indifferent to home and family. The former has
a pantheistic tone about it, due to the lively feeling
of the connection between man and the universe, and a
definite theological stamp owing to its taking a stand
by positive religion; the latter has a rationalistic
character, owing to the enfranchisement of the wise
man from the prejudices of popular belief, with which
it has exclusively to do. In all these respects
Stoicism preserves the original character of the
Socratic philosophy far better than Cynicism, which
only caricatured them. Still it departs from that
character in two respects. In point of theory the
Stoic doctrine received a systematic form and
development such as Socrates never contemplated; and
in natural science, it cultivated a field avoided by
Socrates on principle, however much its doctrine of
Providence, and its view of nature as a system of
means subordinated to ends, may remind of Socrates. On
the other hand, interest in science, although limited
to the subject of ethics, is with Socrates far deeper
and stronger than with the Stoics, the latter pursuing
scientific research only as a means for solving moral
problems. Hence the Socratic theory of a knowledge of
conceptions, simple though it may sound, contained a
fruitful germ of unexpanded speculation, in comparison
with which all that the Stoics did is fragmentary. The
Stoic ethics are not only more expanded and more
carefully worked out in detail than those of Socrates,
but they are also more logical in clinging to the
principle that virtue alone is an unconditional good.
There are no concessions to current modes of thought,
such as Socrates allowed, who practically based his
doctrine of morals upon utility. On the other hand,
the moral science of the Stoics also falls far short
of the frankness and cheerfulness of the Socratic view
of life. If in many respects it toned down the
asperities of Cynicism, still it appropriated its
leading principles far too unreservedly to avoid
accepting a great number of its conclusions.
Asking in the next place in how far the Stoics were
induced by other influences to change and extend the
platform of the Socratic philosophy, we have for
determining the practical side of their system,
besides the general tendency of the post-Aristotelian
philosophy, the example of Cynicism. Its speculative
development, on the other hand, is partly connected
with the Megarians. partly with Heraclitus; to the
Megarians the personal connection of Zeno with Stilpo
points, to Heraclitus the fact that from him the
Stoics themselves deduced their views on natural
science, which they expanded in commentaries on his
writings.
Probably the Megarian influence must not be rated too
high. Zeno may have thence received an impulse to that
reasoning habit which appears with him in a preference
for compressed sharp-pointed syllogisms; but in
post-Aristotelian times, contact with Megarians was
no longer wanted for this, and the greatest reasoner
among the Stoics, Chrysippus, appears not only to have
had no personal relations to them, but his logic is
throughout a simple continuation of that of Aristotle.
Far greater, and more generally recognized, is the
importance of the influence which the views on nature
of the philosopher of Ephesus exercised on the Stoics.
A system which laid such emphasis on the subordination
of everything individual to the law of the universe,
which singled out universal reason from the flux of
things as the one thing everlastingly and permanently
the same--a system in many other ways so nearly
related to their own, must have strongly commended
itself to their notice, and offered them many points
with which to connect their own. If to us the view
that life is dependent for its existence on matter is
repulsive, it was otherwise to the Stoics; for them
this very theory possessed special attractions. Hence,
with the exception of the threefold division of the
elements, there is hardly a single point in the
Heraclitean theory of nature which the Stoics did not
appropriate:--fire or ether as the primary element,
the oneness of this element with universal reason, the
law of the universe, destiny, God, the flux of things,
the gradual change of the primary element into the
four elements, and of these back to the primary
element, the regular alternation of creation and
conflagration in the world, the oneness and eternity
of the universe, the description of the soul as fiery
breath, the identification of the mind with the demon,
the unconditional sovereignty of the universal law
over individuals--these and many other points in the
Stoic system, originally derived from Heraclitus,
prove how greatly this system is indebted to him.
Nor must it be forgotten that there is nothing in
Heraclitus analogous to the reasoning forms of the
Stoics, nor can their ethical views be referred to his
few and undeveloped hints. With all the importance the
Stoics attached to natural science, it is with them
only subordinate to moral science; and the very fact
that it is referred to Heraclitus as its author,
proves its inferior position, and the want of any
independent interest in the subject. It is also
unmistakable that even in natural science the Stoics
only partially follow Heraclitus, and that principles
taken from Heraclitus often bear an altered meaning
when wrought into the Stoic system. Omitting minor
points, not only is the Stoic doctrine of nature in a
formal point of view far more developed, and with
regard to its extension far more comprehensive, than
the corresponding doctrine of Heraclitus, but the
whole Stoic view of the world is by no means so
completely identical with his as might be supposed.
The flux of things, which the Stoics teach equally
with Heraclitus, has not for them that overwhelming
importance that it had for him. The matter of which
the universe consists may be always going over into
new forms, but, at the same time, it is for them the
permanent material and essence of things. Individual
substances, too, are treated by the Stoics as
corporeally permanent. Moreover, from the material
they distinguish the active principle, Reason or
deity, far more definitely than Heraclitus had done,
and the same distinction is carried into individual
things in the contrast between matter and quality.
Thereby it becomes possible for them to contrast much
more sharply than their predecessor had done the
reason of the world, and the blindly working power of
nature. Heraclitus, it would appear, confined his
attention to observing nature and describing its
elementary meteorological processes. But the natural
science of the Stoics includes the idea of means
working for ends. It sees the object in referring the
whole arrangement of the world to man, and it pursues
this line of thought exclusively, neglecting in
consequence science proper. Hence the idea of
sovereign reason or the universal law had not the same
meaning in the minds of both. Heraclitus sees this
reason, primarily and chiefly, in the ordinary
sequence of natural phenomena, in the regularity of
the course by which to each individual phenomenon its
place in the world, its extent and duration are
prescribed--in short, in the unchanging coherence of
nature. Without excluding this aspect in their proofs
of the existence of God and the rule of Providence,
the Stoics attach the chief importance to the
serviceableness of the order of nature. The reason
which rules the world appears in Heraclitus primarily
as a natural power; in the Stoics, as intelligence
working with a purpose. For Heraclitus Nature is the
highest object, the object of independent and absolute
interest; and hence the infinite Being is no more than
the power which forms the world. The Stoics regard
nature from the platform of humanity, as a means for
the wellbeing and activity of man. Their deity
accordingly does not work as a simple power of nature,
but essentially as the wisdom which cares for the
wellbeing of man. The highest conception in the system
of Heraclitus is that of nature or destiny. Stoicism
accepted this conception also, but at the same time
developed it to the higher idea of Providence.
Shall we be wrong if we attribute this modification of
the Heraclitean theory of nature by the Stoics partly
to the influence of Socrates’ and Plato's theory of
final causes, but in a still greater degree to the
influence of the Aristotelian philosophy? To Aristotle
belongs properly the idea of matter without qualities,
no less than the distinction between a material and a
formal Cause. Aristotle applied the idea of purpose to
natural science far more extensively than any other
system had done before; and although the mode in which
the Stoics expressed this idea has more resemblance to
the popular theological statements of Socrates and
Plato than to Aristotle, still the Stoic conception of
a natural power working with a purpose, such as is
contained in the idea of artificial fire and the
generative principle of the Universe, is essentially
Aristotelian. Even many positions which appear to be
advanced in opposition to Aristotle were yet connected
with him. Thus the existence of ether as a body
distinct from the four elements is denied, and yet in
point of fact it is asserted under a new name--that of
artificial fire. The Peripatetic doctrine of the
origin of the rational soul is contradicted by the
Stoic theory of development, and yet the latter is
based on a statement in Aristotle to the effect that
the germ of the animal soul lies in the warm air which
surrounds the seed, warm air which Aristotle
distinguishes from fire quite as carefully as Zeno and
Cleanthes distinguished the two kinds of fire. Even
the point of greatest divergence from Aristotelian
teaching--the transformation of the human soul and the
divine spirit into something corporeal--might yet be
connected with Aristotle, and, indeed, the Peripatetic
School here comes to their assistance. For had not
Aristotle described the ether as the most divine body,
the stars formed out of it as divine and happy beings?
Had he not brought down the acting and moving forces
from a heavenly sphere to the region of earth? Had he
not, as we have just seen, sought the germ of the soul
in an ethereal matter? And might not others go a
little further and arrive at materialistic views? and
all the more so, seeing how hard it is to conceive the
extra-mundane intelligence of Aristotle, at once as
incorporeal, and yet touching and encircling the world
of matter, and to make personal unity in the human
soul accord with an origin in a reason coming from
above?
The way for Stoicism was more directly paved by the
Aristotelian speculations as to the origin of notions
and conceptions. Here the Stoics did little more than
omit (in conformity with their principles) what their
predecessor had said as to an original possession and
immediate knowledge of truth. It has been remarked on
an earlier occasion how closely their formal logic
followed that of Aristotle; they contented themselves
with building on Aristotelian foundations, and even
their additions have more reference to grammar than to
logic. The actual influence of Peripatetic views on
those of the Stoics appears to have been least in the
province of ethics. Here the crudity of the Stoic
conception of virtue, the entire suppression of
emotions, the absolute exclusion of everything
external from the circle of moral goods, the
distinction between the wise and the foolish man, the
attacks on a purely speculative life, present a sharp
contrast to the caution and many-sidedness of
Aristotle's moral theory, to his careful weighing of
current opinions and their practicability, to his
recognition of propriety in every shape and form, and
to the praise which he lavishes on a purely
speculative life. What the Stoics chiefly owe to
Aristotle is the formal treatment of the materials and
the psychological analysis of individual moral
faculties. On the other hand, the province of ethics
must be looked to for traces of the teaching which
Zeno received from Polemo, perhaps even from
Xenocrates.
The speculative portions of Plato’s teaching could
offer no great attractions to practical men and
materialists like the Stoics, either in their original
form or in the form which they assumed in the older
Academy under Pythagorean influence. On the other
hand, such points in Platonism as the Socratic habit
of making knowledge the foundation of virtue, the
comparative depreciation of external goods, the
disparagement of all that is sensual, the elevation
and the purity of moral idealism, and, in the older
Academy, the demand for life according to nature, the
doctrine of the self-sufficingness of virtue, and the
growing tendency to confine philosophy to practical
issues--all these were questions for a Stoic full of
interest. Unfounded as the notion of the later
Eclectics is, that the Stoic and Academician systems
of morality were altogether the same, the Stoics,
nevertheless, appear to have received suggestions from
the Academy which they carried out in a more
determined spirit. Thus the theory of living according
to nature belongs originally to the Academy, although
the Stoics adopted it with a peculiar and somewhat
different meaning. Besides influencing the moral
doctrines of the Stoics, the attitude assumed by the
older Academy towards positive religion may also have
had some influence on their orthodoxy; their most
prominent representative. Cleanthes is in his whole
philosophic character the counterpart of Xenocrates.
Although later in its origin than Stoicism, the new
Academy was not without important influence on that
system, through the person of Chrysippus, but this
influence was at first only of an indirect kind,
inasmuch as it obliged the Stoics by its logical
contradiction to look about for a more logical basis
for their system, and therewith to attempt a more
systematic expansion of their teaching. Somewhat
similar is the effect of Epicureanism, which by its
strong opposition in the field of ethics imparted
decision and accuracy to the Stoic doctrine, and thus
indirectly helped to form it.
By the aid of these remarks it now becomes possible to
give a satisfactory account of the history of
Stoicism. Belonging to an age of moral debasement and
political oppression, its founder, Zeno, conceived the
idea of liberating himself and all who were able to
follow him from its degeneracy and slavery by means of
a philosophy which, by purity and strength of moral
will, would procure independence from all external
things, and unruffled inward peace. That his endeavors
should have taken this practical turn, that he should
have proposed to himself not knowledge as such, but
the moral exercise of knowledge as the object to be
realized, was in part due to his own personal
character, and may be in part referred to the general
circumstances of the times. On nobler and more serious
minds, these circumstances weighed too heavily not to
call forth opposition and resistance in place of
listless contemplation. The sway of the Macedonian,
and afterwards of the Roman Empire, was far too
despotic to allow the least prospect of open
resistance. Nor must it be overlooked that philosophy
itself had reached a pass at which satisfactory
answers to speculative problems were no longer
forthcoming; hence attention was naturally directed to
questions of morals.
Haunted by this longing for virtue, Zeno must have
felt attracted by a system of philosophy which had at
an earlier period followed a similar course with
marked success, viz. the system of the Cynics, and
what he doubtless identified therewith, the old
Socratic teaching. Anxious to find a positive meaning
and scientific basis for virtue, he strove to
appropriate from every system whatever agreed with the
bent of his own mind. By using all the labors of his
predecessors, and keeping his eye steadily fixed upon
the practical end of philosophy, he succeeded in
forming a new and more comprehensive system, which was
afterwards completed by Chrysippus. In point of form
this system was most indebted to the Peripatetic
philosophy; in point of matter, next to its debt to
the Cynics, which has been already mentioned, its
chief obligation was to Heraclitus. But the moral
theory of the Stoics was as little identical with that
of the Cynics, as the natural science of the Stoics
was with that of Heraclitus. If the divergence was, in
the first instance, due to the influence of the Stoic
principles, still the influence of the Peripatetic
teaching is unmistakable in the natural and
speculative science of the Stoics, and the influence
of the Academy in their moral science. Stoicism does
not, therefore, appear simply as a continuation of
Cynicism, nor yet as an isolated innovation, but, like
every other form of thought which marks an epoch, it
worked up into itself all previous materials, and
produced from their combination a new result. In this
process of assimilation much that was beautiful and
full of meaning was omitted; everything was absorbed
that could be of use in the new career on which the
Greek mind was about to enter.
It was the fault of the age that it could no longer
come up to the many-sidedness of an Aristotle or a
Plato. Stoicism, it is true, approximates thereto more
nearly than any other of the post-Aristotelian
systems. But in its practical view of philosophy, in
its materialistic appeal to the senses, in its
theoretical self-sufficiency, setting up the wise man
as superior to the weaknesses and wants of human
nature; in its citizenship of the world, throwing
political interests into the background; and in so
many other traits it is the fit exponent of an epoch
in which the taste for purely scientific research and
the delight in ethical speculation were at an end,
whilst out of the overthrow of states, and the growth
of freedom, the idea of humanity was coming to the
fore. Stoicism represented most powerfully the moral
and religious convictions of such an age, yet not
without onesidedness and exaggeration. By exercise of
the will and by rational understanding, man is to
become free and happy. This aim is, however, pursued
so persistently that the natural conditions of human
existence and the claims of individuality are ignored.
To man, regarded as the exponent of universal law, as
little freedom of will is allowed by the Stoic natural
science in face of the inexorable course of nature as
freedom of action is allowed by the Stoic ethics in
face of the demands of duty. The universal claims of
morality are alone acknowledged; the right of the
individual to act according to his peculiar character,
and to develop that character, is almost ignored. The
individual, as such, dwindles into obscurity, whilst a
high place in the world is assigned to mankind
collectively. The individual is subordinated to the
law of the whole; but by regarding nature as a system
of means and ends, and introducing the belief in
Providence and Prophecy, the universe is again
subordinated to the interests of man--a view against
which a more careful research has many objections to
urge. In both respects Epicureanism is in decided
contrast to Stoicism, though agreeing with it in the
general tone of its practical philosophy and in its
aim to make man independent of the outer world and
happy in himself.
PART III. THE EPICUREANS.
Chapter XV. Epicurus and the Epicurean School.
EPICURUS, the son of the Athenian Neocles,
was born in Samos in the year 342 or 341 B.C. His
early education appears to have been neglected; and
his knowledge of previous philosophic systems was very
superficial, even at the time when he first came
forward as an independent teacher. Still he can hardly
have been so entirely self-taught as he wished to
appear at a later period in life. The names, at least,
of the individuals are on record who instructed him in
the systems of Democritus and Plato; and although it
is by no means an ascertained fact that he
subsequently attended the lectures of Xenocrates, on
the occasion of a visit to Athens, no doubt can be
felt that he was acquainted with the writings of
previous philosophers, from whom he borrowed important
parts of his system and more particularly with those
of Democritus.
After having been engaged as a teacher in several
Schools in Asia Minor, he repaired to Athens about the
year 306 B.C., and there founded a School of his own.
The meeting-place of this School was the founder’s
garden, and its center of attraction was the founder
himself, around whom a circle of friends gathered,
knit together by a common set of principles, by a
common affection for a master whom they almost
worshipped, and by a common enjoyment of cultivated
society. Opponents charged the Epicureans with gross
impropriety, because they admitted not only women, but
women of loose morality, to this circle of philosophic
culture; but in the then state of Greek society, such
conduct does not appear extraordinary. Here Epicurus
labored for six and thirty years, during which he
succeeded in impressing a stamp on his School which is
now seen definite and unchanged after the lapse of
centuries. In the year 270 B.C. he succumbed to
disease, the pains and troubles of which he bore with
great fortitude. Out of the multitude of his writings
only a few have come down to us, and these are for the
most part unimportant ones. On the whole, these
fragments bear out the unfavorable opinions which
opponents have expressed with regard to his style.
Among the numerous scholars of Epicurus the best known
are Metrodorus and Polyaenus, both of whom died before
their master; Hermarchus, upon whom the presidency of
the School devolved after the death of Epicurus; and
Colotes, against whom Plutarch, four hundred years
later, wrote a treatise. Many others are also known,
at least by name. The garden which Epicurus in his
will left to the School continued after his death to
be the external rallying-point for his followers.
Hermarchus was succeeded by Polystratus, with whom
Hippoclides is also mentioned as joint-president.
Hermarchus and Hippoclides were succeeded by
Dionysius, and Dionysius again by Basilides.
Protarchus of Bargylium, and his pupil, Demetrius the
Laconian, appear to belong to the second century
before Christ; but the time in which these
philosophers flourished cannot be established with
certainty; and the same remark applies to several
others whose names are on record.
Before the middle of the second century B.C.
Epicureanism is said to have obtained a footing in
Rome. It is certain that it existed there not long
afterwards. C. Amafinius is mentioned as the first who
paved the way for the spread of Epicurean doctrines by
discussing them in Latin; and it is stated that these
doctrines soon found many supporters, attracted partly
by their merits, but more often by the simplicity and
the ease with which they could be understood.
Towards the close of the second century Apollodorus,
one of the most voluminous writers on philosophy,
taught at Athens. His pupil, Zeno of Sidon, the most
important among the Epicureans of that age, labored
for a long time successfully, both orally and in
writing. About the same time Phaedrus is heard of in
Rome and Athens, and at a little later period
Philodemus, and Syro or Sciro in Rome, and Patro, the
successor of Phaedrus, in Athens. The number of
Epicureans at Rome, known to us chiefly from Cicero’s
writings, is not small. No one of them has obtained a
higher repute than T. Lucretius Carus. His poem,
carefully reproducing the Epicurean notions on natural
science, is one of the most valuable sources for the
knowledge of their system. Contemporary with Lucretius
was the celebrated physician Asclepiades of Bithynia,
who resided at Rome, but to judge by the views on
nature attributed to him, he was no genuine Epicurean,
although connected with the Epicurean School.
In the following century several supporters of the
practical philosophy of the Epicureans are known to
us, but no one apparently approaching Zeno or Phaedrus
in scientific importance. Rehabilitated under the
Antonines by the establishment of a public chair in
Athens, the Epicurean School outlived most other
systems, and continued to exist as late as the fourth
century after Christ.
Chapter XVI. Character and Divisions of the
Epicurean Teaching: The Test-Science of Truth.
THE scientific value and capacity for
development of Epicureanism are out of all proportion
to its extensive diffusion and the length of time
during which it continued to flourish. No other system
troubled itself so little about the foundation on
which it rested; none confined itself so exclusively
to the utterances of its founder. Such was the
dogmatism with which Epicnrus propounded his precepts,
such the conviction he entertained of their
excellence, that his pupils were required to commit
summaries of them to memory; and the superstitious
devotion for the founder was with his approval carried
to such a length, that on no single point was the
slightest deviation from his tenets permitted.
Although, even in Cicero’s time, the writings of
Epicurus and Metrodorus found hardly a reader outside
the School, yet it is asserted that as late as the
first and second centuries after Christ the Epicureans
clung tenaciously to their master’s teaching. Probably
it was easier for an Epicurean than for any other
thinker to act thus. Like his master, he was
indifferent to the labors of other philosophers, or
unable to appreciate their merits. For us this conduct
of theirs has one advantage: we can be far more
certain that the Epicurean teaching reflects that of
the founder than we can that this is so in the case of
the Stoics. But this philosophical sterility, this
mechanical handing down of unchangeable principles,
places the intellectual value of Epicureanism on the
lowest level. The servile dependence of the Epicurean
School on its founder can neither excuse its mental
idleness nor recommend a system so powerless to give
an independent training to its supporters.
The want of intellectual taste here displayed appears
also in the view taken by Epicurus of the aim and
business of philosophy. If among the Stoics the
subordination of theory to practice was frequently
felt, among the Epicureans this subordination was
carried to such an extent as to lead to a depreciation
of all science. The aim of philosophy was. with them,
to promote human happiness. Indeed, philosophy is
nothing else than an activity helping us to happiness
by means of speech and thought. Nor is happiness,
according to Epicurus, directly promoted by knowledge,
but only indirectly in as far as knowledge ministers
to practical needs, or clears away hindrances to their
attainment. All science which does not serve this end
is superfluous and worthless. Epicurus, therefore,
despised learning and culture, the researches of
grammarians, and the lore of historians, and declared
it a piece of good fortune for simplicity of feeling
to be uncontaminated by learned rubbish. Nor was his
opinion different respecting mathematical science, of
which he was wholly ignorant. The calculations of
mathematicians, he maintained, are based on false
principles; at any rate, they contribute nothing to
human happiness, and it is therefore useless and
foolish to trouble oneself about them. The theory of
music and poetry he likewise found exceedingly
irksome, although he took pleasure in music itself and
the theater; and rhetoric, as an artificial guide to
eloquence, seemed to him as worthless as the
show-speeches which are the only result of the study
of it. The power of public speaking is a matter of
practice and of momentary feeling, and hence the
skillful speaker is far from being a good statesman.
The greater part of logical inquiries fared no better
in his judgment. Himself no logician, he set little
store by logic. Definitions are of no use: the theory
of division and proof may be dispensed with: the
philosopher does best to confine himself to words, and
to leave all the logical ballast alone. Of all the
questions which engrossed the attention of Stoic
logicians, one only, the theory of knowledge, was
studied by Epicurus, and that in a very superficial
way.
Far greater, comparatively, was the importance he
attached to the study of nature, but even natural
science was deemed valuable not so much for its own
sake as because of its practical use. The knowledge of
natural causes is the only means of liberating the
soul from the shackles of superstition; this is the
only use of natural science. If it were not for the
thought of God and the fear of death, there would be
no need of studying nature. The investigation of our
instincts is also of use, because it helps us to
control them, and to keep them within their natural
bounds. Thus the one-sided practical view of
philosophy which we have already encountered in
Stoicism was carried by the Epicureans to an extreme
length.
Nor is it otherwise than in harmony herewith that
logic did not receive a fuller or more perfect
treatment in the further development of their system.
Even the study of nature, going far more fully into
particulars than logic, was guided entirely by
practical considerations, all scientific interest in
nature being ignored. Following the usual method,
however, the Epicureans divided philosophy into three
parts--logic, natural science, and moral science.
Limiting the first of these parts to one branch of
logic, the part which deals with the characteristics
of truth, and which they therefore called neither
logic, nor dialectic, but Canonic, they really reduced
this part to a mere introductory appendage to the two
other parts, and studied Canonic as a part of natural
science. Natural science moreover was so entirely
subordinated to moral science, that we might almost
feel tempted to follow some modern writers in their
view of the Epicurean system, by giving to moral
science precedence of the two other parts, or at least
of natural science. The School, however, followed the
usual order, and not without reason; for although the
whole tendency of the Epicurean Canonic and natural
science can only, like the Stoic, be explained by a
reference to moral science, yet moral science with
them presupposes the test-science of truth and
natural science. We shall, therefore, do well to treat
of Canonic in the first place, and subsequently to
prove how this branch of study depends on Ethics.
Canonic or the test-science of truth, as has been
observed, is occupied with investigating the standard
of truth, and with inquiring into the mode of
acquiring knowledge. The whole of formal logic, the
doctrine of the formation of conceptions and
conclusions, is omitted by Epicurus. Even the theory
of the acquisition of knowledge assumes with him a
very simple form. If the Stoics were fain,
notwithstanding their ideal ethics and their
pantheistic speculations, ultimately to take their
stand on materialism, could Epicurus avoid doing the
same? In seeking a speculative basis for a view of
life which refers everything to the feeling of
pleasure or pain, he appealed far more unreservedly
than they had done to sensation. Now, since the senses
can alone inform us what is pleasant or unpleasant,
and what is desirable or the contrary, our judgment as
to truth or falsehood must ultimately depend on the
senses. Viewed speculatively, sensation is the
standard of truth; viewed practically, the feeling of
pleasure or pain. If the senses may not be trusted,
still less may knowledge derived from reason be
trusted, since reason itself is primarily and entirely
derived from the senses. There remains, therefore, no
distinctive mark of truth, and no possibility of
certain conviction. We are at the mercy of unlimited
doubt. If, however, this doubt, is contradictory of
itself--for how can men declare they know, that they
can know nothing?--it is also contradictory of human
nature, since it would do away not only with all
knowledge but with every possibility of action--in
short, with all the conditions on which human life
depends. To avoid doubt we must allow that sensation
as such is always, and under all circumstances, to be
trusted; nor ought the delusions of the senses to
shake our belief; the causes of these deceptions do
not lie in sensation as such, but in our judgment
about sensation. What the senses supply is only that
an object produces this or that effect upon us, and
that this or that picture has impressed our soul. The
facts thus supplied are always true, only it does not
follow that the object exactly corresponds with the
impression we receive of it, or that it produces on
others the same impression that it produces on us.
Many different pictures may emanate from one and the
same object, and these pictures may be changed on
their way to the ear or eye. Pictures, too, may strike
our senses with which no real objects correspond. To
confound the picture with the thing, the impression
made with the object making the impression, is
certainly an error, but this error must not be laid to
the charge of the senses, but to that of opinion.
Indeed, how is it possible, asks Epicurus, to refute
the testimony of the senses? Can reason refute it? But
reason is itself dependent on the senses, and cannot
bear testimony against that on which its own claims to
belief depend. Or can one sense convict another of
error? But different sensations do not refer to the
same object, and similar sensations have equal value.
Nothing remains, therefore, but to attach implicit
belief to every impression of the senses. Every such
impression is directly certain, and is accordingly
termed by Epicurus clear evidence. Nay, more, its
truth is so paramount that the impressions of madmen,
and appearances in dreams, are true because they are
caused by something real, and error only becomes
possible when we go beyond sensation.
This going beyond sensation becomes, however, a
necessity. By a repetition of the same perception a
notion arises. A notion, therefore, is nothing else
than the general picture retained in the mind of what
has been perceived. On these notions retained by
memory depend all speaking and thinking. They are what
commonly go under the name of things; and speech is
only a means of recalling definite perceptions to the
memory. Notions are presupposed in all scientific
knowledge. Together with sensations they form the
measure of the truth of our convictions; and it holds
true of them as it did of sensations--that they are
true in themselves and need no proof. Taken by
themselves, notions, like perceptions, are reflections
in the soul of things on which the transforming action
of the mind, changing external impressions into
conceptions, has not as yet been brought to bear.
For this very reason notions are not sufficient. From
appearances we must advance to their secret causes;
from the known to the unknown. Far too little value
was attached by Epicurus to the logical forms of
thought, or he would have investigated more accurately
the nature of this process of advancing. Thoughts, in
his view, result from sensations spontaneously, and
although a certain amount of reflection is necessary
for the process, yet it requires no scientific
guidance. The thoughts arrived at in this way do not
stand as a higher genus above perceptions, but they
are only opinions without a note of truth in
themselves, and depending for their truth upon
sensation. That opinion may be considered a true one
which is based on the testimony of the senses, or is
at least not contrary to the senses, and that a false
opinion in which the opposite is the case. Sometimes
we suppose that upon certain present impressions other
impressions will follow: for instance, that a tower
which appears round at a distance will appear round
close at hand. In that case, if the real perception
corresponds with the assumption, the opinion is true,
otherwise it is false. At other times we suppose that
certain appearances are due to secret causes: for
instance, that empty space is the cause of motion. If
all appearances tally with their explanations, we may
consider our assumptions correct; if not, our
assumptions are incorrect. In the first case the test
of the truth of an opinion is that it is supported by
experience; in the latter that it is not refuted by
experience. Have we not here all the leading features
of a theory of knowledge based purely on sensation?
The Epicurean's interest in these questions was,
however, far too slight to construct with them a
developed theory of materialism.
Little pains seem to have been taken by Epicurus to
overcome the difficulties by which this view was
beset. If all sensations as such are true, the saying
of Protagoras necessarily follows that for each
individual that is true which seems to him to be true,
that contrary impressions about one and the same
object are true, and that deceptions of the senses, so
many instances of which are supplied by experience,
are really impossible. To avoid these conclusions,
Epicurus maintained that for each different impression
there is a different object-picture. What immediately
affects our senses is not the object itself, but a
picture of the object, and these pictures may be
innumerable, a different one being the cause of each
separate sensation. Moreover, although the pictures
emanating from the same object are in general nearly
alike, it is possible that they may differ from one
another owing to a variety of causes. If, therefore,
the same object appears different to different
individuals, the cause of these different sensations
is not one and the same, but a different one, and
different pictures must have affected their senses. If
our own sensations deceive us, the blame does not
belong to our senses, as though they had depicted to
us unreal objects, but to our judgment for drawing
unwarranted inferences from pictures as to their
causes.
This line of argument, however, only removes the
difficulty one step further. Sensation is said always
to reproduce faithfully the picture which affects the
organs of sense, but the picture's do not always
reproduce the object with equal faithfulness. How then
can a faithful picture be known from one which is not
faithful? To this question the Epicurean system can
furnish no real answer. To say that the wise man knows
how to distinguish a faithful from an unfaithful
picture is to despair of an absolute standard at all,
and to make the decision of truth or error depend upon
the individual's judgment. Such a statement reduces
all our impressions of the properties of things to a
relative level. If sensation does not show us things
themselves, but only those impressions of them which
happen to affect us, it does not supply us with a
knowledge of things as they are, but as they happen to
be related to us. It was, therefore, a legitimate
inference from this theory of knowledge for Epicurus
to deny that color belongs to bodies in themselves,
since some only see color in the dark, whilst others
do not. Like his predecessor, Democritus, he must have
been brought to this view by his theory of atoms. Few
of the properties belong to atoms which we perceive in
things, and hence all other properties must be
explained as not belonging to the essence, but only to
the appearance of things. The taste for speculation
was, however, too weak, and the need of a direct truth
of the senses too strong in Epicurus for him to be
able to turn his thoughts in this direction for long.
Whilst allowing to certain properties of things only a
relative value, he had no wish to doubt the reality of
objects, nor to disparage the object-pictures which
furnish us with sensations.
Chapter XVII. The Epicurean Views on Nature.
IF Epicurus and his followers underrated
logic, to natural science they attached a considerable
value. This value was, however, exclusively derived
from a sense of the practical advantages which a
knowledge of nature confers in opposing superstition.
Without such an object the study of nature would have
seemed wholly superfluous. Such being their attitude
of mind, the Epicureans were, as might have been
expected, indifferent, about giving a complete and
accurate explanation of phenomena. Their one aim was
to put forward such a view of nature as would do away
with the necessity for supernatural intervention,
without at the same time pretending to offer a
sufficient solution of the problems raised by science.
Whilst, therefore, he devoted considerable attention
to natural science, Epicurus does not seem to have
considered certainty to be of importance, or even to
be possible, in dealing with details of scientific
study. Of the general causes of things we can and
ought to entertain a firm conviction, since the
possibility of overcoming religious prejudices and the
fears occasioned by them depends on these convictions.
No such result, however, follows from the
investigation of details, which, on the contrary, only
tends to confirm prejudices in those who are not
already emancipated from them. In dealing with
details, therefore, it is enough for Epicurus to show
that various natural causes for phenomena may be
imagined, and to offer various suggestions which
dispense with the intervention of the Gods and the
myths of a belief in Providence. To say that any one
of these suggestions is the only possible one, is in
most cases to exceed the bounds of experience and
human knowledge, and to go back to the capricious
explanations of mythology. Possibly the world may
move, and possibly it may be at rest. Possible it may
be round, or else it may be triangular, or have any
other shape. Possibly the sun and the stars may be
extinguished at setting, and be lighted afresh at
rising. It is, however, equally possible that they may
only disappear under the earth and reappear again, or
that their rising and setting may be due to yet other
causes. Possibly the waxing and waning of the moon may
be caused by the moon’s revolving; or it may be due to
an atmospheric change, or to an actual increase and
decrease in the moon’s size, or to some other cause.
Possibly the moon may shine with borrowed light, or it
may shine with its own, experience supplying us with
instances of bodies which give their own light, and of
those which have their light borrowed. From these and
such-like statements it appears that questions of
natural science in themselves have no value for
Epicurus. Whilst granting that only one natural
explanation of phenomena is generally possible, yet in
any particular case he is perfectly indifferent which
explanation is adopted.
Great stress is, however, laid by him on the general
explanation. In contrast with the religious view which
regards the world as a system of means leading to
ends, the leading business of the natural science of
the Epicureans is to refer all phenomena to natural
causes. To an Epicurean nothing appears more absurd
than to suppose that the arrangements of nature have
for their object the well-being of mankind, or that
they have any object at all. The tongue is not given
us for the purpose of speaking, nor the ears for the
purpose of hearing. As a matter of fact, it would,
indeed, be more correct to say, that we speak because
we have a tongue, and hear because we have ears.
Natural powers have acted purely according to the law
of necessity, and among their various products there
could not fail to be some presenting the appearance of
purpose in their arrangement. In the case of man there
have resulted many such products and powers. But this
result is by no means intentional; it is an accidental
consequence of natural causes. In explaining nature
all thought of Gods must be put out of sight. For
their happiness would be inconceivable, on the
supposition that they cared for man and his welfare.
Confining his interest in nature, as Epicurus did,
entirely to this general view of things, he was all
the more inclined, in carrying it into details, to
rely upon some older system. No system, however,
appeared to correspond better with his tone of mind
than that of Democritus, which, moreover, commended
itself to him not only by absolutely banishing the
idea of final cause, but by referring everything to
matter, and by its theory of atoms. As Epicurus places
in each individual thing taken by itself the ultimate
end of action, so Democritus had theoretically made
all that is real to consist in what is absolutely
individual or in atoms. His natural science,
therefore, seemed to present the most natural basis
for the Epicurean Ethics. If the Stoics, in their
views of nature, closely followed Heraclitus, Epicurus
in his followed Democritus still mere closely, and
hence, with the exception of one single point, the
additions made by Epicurus to the theory of this
philosopher are of no philosophical importance.
With Democritus Epicurus agreed in holding that there
is no other form of reality except that of bodily
reality. Every substance, he says in the words of the
Stoics, must affect others, and be affected by them;
and whatever affects others or is itself affected, is
corporeal. Corporeal substance is, therefore, the only
kind of substance The various qualities of things,
essential as well as accidental qualities, are
accordingly not incorporeal existences, but simply
chance modes of body, the former being called by
Epicurus accidental properties, the latter symptoms.
But a second something is necessary besides corporeal
substance in order to explain phenomena, viz. empty
space. That empty space exists is proved by the
differences of weight in bodies. For what else could
be the cause of this difference? It is proved still
more conclusively by motion, motion being impossible
without empty space. Mind as a moving cause, however,
seems to Epicurus altogether superfluous. Everything
that exists consists of bodies and empty space, and
there is no third thing.
Democritus had resolved the two conceptions of body
and empty space into the conceptions of being and not
being. True to his position, Epicurus dispensed with
this speculative basis, and clinging to the ordinary
notions of empty space, and of a material filling
space, he simply proves these notions by the qualities
of phenomena. For this very reason Democritus’s
division of body into innumerable primary particles or
atoms appeared to him most necessary. All bodies known
to us by sensation are composed of parts. If the
process of division were infinitely continued, all
things would ultimately be resolved into the
non-existent--in this Epicurus and Democritus
agree;--and conversely all things must have been
formed out of the non-existent, in defiance of the
first principle of natural science that nothing can
come from nothing, and that nothing can be resolved
into nothing. Hence, we must conclude that the primary
component parts of things can neither have come into
existence nor cease to exist, nor yet be changed in
their nature. These primary bodies contain no empty
space in themselves, and hence can neither be divided
nor destroyed, nor be changed in any way. They are so
small that they do not impress the senses, and as a
matter of fact we do not see them. Nevertheless they
must not be regarded as mathematical atoms, the name
atoms being assigned to them only because their bodily
structure will not admit of division. They have
neither color, warmth, smell, nor any other property;
properties belong only to distinct materials; and for
this reason they must not be sought in the four
elements, all of which, as experience shows, come into
being and pass away. They possess only the universal
qualities of all corporeal things, viz. shape, size,
and weight.
Not only must atoms, like all other bodies, have
shape, but there must exist among them indefinitely
many varieties of shape, or it would be impossible to
account for the innumerable differences of things.
There cannot, however, be really an infinite number of
shapes, as Democritus maintained, in any limited
body--this is intelligible of itself--nor yet in the
whole universe, since an unlimited number would make
the arrangement of the world impossible, everything in
the world being circumscribed by certain containing
limits. Again, atoms must be different in point of
size; for all materials cannot be divided into
particles of equal size. Yet even to this difference
there must be some limitation. An atom must neither be
so large as to become an object of sense, nor can it,
after what has been said, be infinitely small. From
difference in point of size the difference of atoms in
point of weight follows. In point of number atoms must
be innumerable, and in the same way empty space must
be unbounded also. For since everything bounded must
be bounded by something, it is impossible to imagine
any bounds of the universe beyond which nothing
exists, and hence there can be no bounds at all. The
absence of bounds must apply to the mass of atoms
quite as much as to empty space. If an infinite number
of atoms would not find room in a limited space,
conversely a limited number of atoms would be lost in
empty space, and never able to form a world. In all
these views Epicurus closely follows Democritus, no
doubt agreeing with him also in explaining the
qualities of things by the composition of their atoms.
In deducing the origin of things from their primary
causes, Epicurus, however, deviates widely from his
predecessor. Atoms--so it was taught by both--have by
virtue of their weight been eternally engaged in a
downward motion. That all bodies should move downwards
in empty space seemed to Epicurus a matter of course;
for whatever is heavy must fall unless it is
supported. He was therefore opposed to the
Aristotelian view that heaviness shows itself in the
form of attraction towards a center, and consequently
to his further supposition that downward mode of
motion belongs only to certain bodies, circular motion
being for others more natural. The objection that in
endless space there is no above or below he could meet
only by appealing to experience; some things always
appear above our heads, others beneath our feet. But
whilst Democritus held that atoms in their downward
motion meet together, thus giving rise to a rotatory
motion, no such view commended itself to Epicurus. Nay
rather in his view all atoms will fall equally fast,
since empty space offers no resistance, and falling
perpendicularly it is impossible to see how they can
meet. To render a meeting possible he supposes the
smallest possible swerving aside from the
perpendicular line in falling. This assumption seemed
to him indispensable, since it would be otherwise
impossible to assert the freedom of the human will.
For how can the will be free if everything falls
according to the strict law of gravity? For the same
reason this swerving aside was not supposed to proceed
from any natural necessity, but simply from the power
of self-motion in the atoms. In consequence of their
meeting one part of the atoms rebounds--so Democritus
also taught; the lighter ones are forced upwards, and
from the upward and downward motions combined a
rotatory motion arises. When this motion takes place a
clustering of atoms is the consequence, which by their
own motion separate themselves from the remaining
mass, and form a world of themselves. Atoms being
eternal and unchangeable, the process of forming
worlds must go on without beginning or end; and
inasmuch as they are also infinite in number, and
empty space is infinite also, there must be an
innumerable number of worlds. In the character of
these worlds the greatest possible variety may be
supposed, since it is most unlikely that the
innumerable combinations of atoms all brought about at
random will fall out alike. Equally impossible is it
to assert that all these worlds are absolutely
dissimilar. In general, Epicurus assumed that they are
extremely different both in point of size and
arrangement, and that here and there one may be
similar to our own. Moreover, since eternity affords
time for all imaginable combinations of atoms, nothing
can ever be brought about now which has not already
existed. In one respect all worlds are alike; they
come into existence, are liable to decay, and, like
all other individual elements, are exposed to a
gradual increase and decrease. So we might have
assumed from other positions in his system. Between
the individual worlds both Democritus and Epicurus
insert intermediate world-spaces, in which by the
clustering of atoms from time to time new worlds come
into being.
The origin of our world is thus described. At a
certain period of time--Lucretius believes at no very
distant period--a cluster of atoms of varying shape
and size was formed in this definite portion of space.
These atoms meeting there first arose from the
pressure and rebound of the quickly falling particles
motions of every variety in every direction. Soon the
greater atoms pressing downwards, by dint of weight
forced upwards the smaller and lighter atoms, the
fiery ones topmost and with the greatest impetus to
form the ether, and afterwards those which form the
air. The upper pressure ceasing, these masses, under
the pressure of particles still joining it from below,
spread forth sidewards, and thus the belts of fire and
air were formed. Next uprose those atoms out of which
the sun and stars are formed into the heights, and at
the same time the earth settled down, its inner part
being partially exhausted in those places where the
sea now is. By the influence of the warmth of the
ether, and the sun-heat, the earth-mass was bound
together more closely, the sea was pressed out of it,
and the surface assumed an uneven character. The world
is shut off from other worlds and from empty space by
those bodies which form its external boundary.
Asking, in the next place, what idea must be formed of
the arrangement of the world, we are met by the two
principles which Epicurus is never weary of
inculcating; one, that we must explain nothing as an
intentional arrangement by deity, but refer everything
simply and solely to mechanical causes; the other,
that in explaining phenomena the widest, possible room
must be given for hypotheses of every kind, and that
nothing is more absurd than to abridge the wide range
of possible explanations by exclusively deciding in
favor of any one. Thereby the investigation of nature
loses for him its value as such, nor is it of any
great interest to us to follow his speculations on
nature into detail. On one point he dogmatizes,
protesting that the framework of heaven must not be
considered the work of God, nor must life and reason
be attributed to the stars. Otherwise, on nearly all
the questions which engaged the attention of
astronomers at that time, he observes the greatest
indifference, treating the views of his predecessors,
good and bad alike, with an easy superficiality which
can only be explained by supposing him altogether
indifferent as to their truth. The state of his own
astronomical knowledge can, moreover, be easily seen
by recalling the notorious assertion that the sun, the
moon, and the stars are either not at all, or only a
little larger, and may possibly be even less than they
appear to be. The Epicureans also thought to support
their theory that the earth, borne by the air, reposes
in the middle of the world--a theory which on their
hypothesis of the weight of bodies is impossible--by
the gradual diminution in weight of the surrounding
bodies. It would be impossible here to go through the
treatment which they gave to atmospheric and
terrestrial phenomena, particularly as the principle
already indicated was most freely used, and many
explanations were given as being all equally possible.
Out of the newly made earth plants at first grew, and
afterwards animals came forth, since the latter,
according to Lucretius, can by no possibility have
fallen from heaven. In other worlds, likewise, living
beings came into existence, though not necessarily in
all. Among these beings were originally, as Empedocles
had previously supposed, all sorts of composite or
deformed creatures. Those, however, alone continued to
exist which were fitted by nature to find support, to
propagate, and to protect themselves from danger.
Romantic creatures, such as centaurs or chimeras, can
never have existed here, because the beings of which
they are compounded would require conditions of life
altogether different.
Aiming, as the Epicureans did, at explaining the
origin of men and animals in a purely natural manner,
they likewise tried to form an idea, equally according
to nature, of the original state and historical
development of the human race. In this attempt they
ignored all legendary notions, and, notwithstanding
their leaning towards materialism, they on the whole
advocated perfectly sound views. The men of early
times, so thought Lucretius, were stronger and more
powerful than the men of to-day. Rude and ignorant as
beasts, they lived in the woods in a perpetual state
of warfare with the wild animals, without justice or
society. The first and most important step in a social
direction was the discovery of fire, the learning to
build huts, and to clothe themselves in skins; then
began marriage and domestic life, and speech,
originally not a matter of convention, but, like the
noises of animals, the natural expression of thoughts
and feelings, was developed. The older the human race
grew, the more they learned of the arts and skill
which minister to the preservation and enjoyment of
life. These arts were first learned by experience,
under the pressure of nature, or the compulsion of
want. What had thus been discovered was completed by
reflection, the more gifted preceding the rest as
teachers. In exactly the same way civil society was
developed. Individuals built strongholds, and made
themselves rulers. In time the power of kings aroused
envy, and they were massacred. To crush the anarchy
which then arose, magistrates were chosen, and order
established by penal laws. It will subsequently be
seen that Epicurus explained religion in the same way
by natural growth.
The apotheosis of nature, which has been apparent in
Epicurus's whole view of history, becomes specially
prominent in his treatment of psychology. This
treatment could, after all that has been said, be only
purely materialistic. The soul, like every other real
being, is a body. In support of this view the
Epicureans appealed to the mutual relations of the
body and the soul, agreeing on this point with the
Stoics. The body of the soul, however, consists of the
finest, lightest, and most easily moved atoms, as is
manifest from the speed of thought, from the
instantaneous dissolution of the soul after death,
and, moreover, from the fact that the soulless body is
as heavy as the body in which there is a soul. Hence
Epicurus, again agreeing with the Stoics, describes
the soul as a material resembling fire and air, or,
more accurately, as composed of four elements, fire,
air, vapor, and a fourth nameless element. It consists
of the finest atoms, and is the cause of feeling, and
according as one or other of these elements
preponderates, the character of man is of one or the
other kind. Like the Stoics, Epicurus believed that
the soul-element is received by generation from the
parents’ souls, and that it is reread over the whole
body, growing as the body grows. At the same time he
makes a distinction somewhat similar to that made by
the Stoics in their doctrine of the sovereign part of
the soul. Only the irrational part of the soul is
diffused as a principle of life over the whole body;
the rational part has its seat in the breast. To the
rational part belong mental activity, sensation, and
perception, the motion of the will and the mind, and
in this latter sense life itself; both parts together
make up one being, yet they may exist in different
conditions. The mind may be cheerful whilst the body
and the irrational soul feel pain, or the reverse may
be the case. It is even possible that portions of the
irrational soul may be lost by the mutilation of the
body, without detriment to the rational soul, or
consequently to life. When, however, the connection
between soul and body is fully severed, then the soul
can no longer exist. Deprived of the surrounding
shelter of the body, its atoms are dispersed in a
moment, owing to their lightness; and the body in
consequence, being unable to exist without the soul,
goes over into corruption. If this view appears to
hold out the most gloomy prospect for the future,
Epicurus considers that it cannot really be so. With
death every feeling of evil ceases, and the time when
we shall no longer exist affects us just as little as
the time before we existed. Nay, more, he entertains
the opinion that his teaching alone can reconcile us
to death by removing all fear of the nether world and
its terrors.
Allowing that many of these statements are natural
consequences of the principles of Epicurus, the
distinction between a rational and an irrational soul
must, nevertheless, at first sight, seem strange in a
system so thoroughly materialistic as was that of the
Epicureans. And yet this distinction is not stranger
than the corresponding parts of the Stoic teaching. If
the Stoic views may be referred to the distinction
which they drew in morals between the senses and the
reason, not less are the Epicurean ethics marked by
the same contrast between the general and the sensuous
side of the mind. Hence Epicurus shares the Stoic
belief in an ethereal origin of the human race; and
although this belief as at first expressed only
implies that man, like other living beings, is
composed of ethereal elements, yet there is connected
with it the distinction already discussed in the case
of the Stoics between the higher and the lower parts
of man, which ultimately comes to be simply another
mode of expressing the difference between mind and
matter.
Among the phenomena of the soul's life, sensation is
made to harmonize with the general principles of the
Epicurean view of nature by the aid of Democritus's
doctrine of atom-pictures. From the surface of
bodies--this is the pith of that doctrine--the finest
possible particles are constantly being thrown off,
which by virtue of their fineness traverse the
furthest spaces in an infinitely short time, hurrying
through the void. Many of these exhalations are
arrested by some obstacle soon after coming forth, or
are otherwise thrown into confusion. In the case of
others the atoms for a long time retain the same
position and connection which they had in bodies
themselves, thus presenting a picture of things, and
only lacking corporeal solidity. As these pictures are
conveyed to the soul by the various organs of sense,
our impressions of things arise. Even those
impressions, which have no corresponding real object,
must be referred to such pictures present in the soul.
For often pictures last longer than things themselves;
and often by a casual combination of atoms pictures
are formed in the air resembling no one single thing.
Sometimes, too, pictures of various kinds are combined
on their way to the senses; thus, for instance, the
notion of a Centaur is caused by the union of the
picture of a man with that of a horse, not only in our
imagination, but already previously in the
atom-picture. If, therefore, sensation distorts or
imperfectly represents real objects, it must be
explained as being due to some change or mutilation in
the atom-pictures before they reach our senses.
In thus (explaining mental impressions, the Epicureans
do not allow themselves to be disturbed by the fact
that we can recall at pleasure the ideas of all
possible things. The cause of this power was rather
supposed to be the circumstance that we are always
surrounded by an innumerable number of atom-pictures,
none of which we perceive unless our attention is
directed to them. Likewise the seeming motion of forms
which we behold in dreams is explained by the hasty
succession of similar atom-pictures, appearing to us
as changes of one and the same picture. But besides
receiving pictures supplied from without, spontaneous
motion with regard to these pictures takes place on
our part, a motion connected in the first instance
with the soul's motion when it receives the outward
impression, but not to be regarded as a simple
continuation thereof. This independent motion gives
rise to opinion, and hence opinion is not so necessary
or so universally true as feeling. It may agree with
feeling, or it may not agree with it. It may be true
or it may be false. The conditions of its being true
or false have been previously investigated.
Impressions also give rise to will and action, the
soul being set in motion by impressions, and this
motion extending from the soul to the body. Into the
nature of will, however, Epicurus does not appear to
have instituted a more careful psychological
investigation. It was enough for him to assert the
freedom of the will. This freedom he considers
absolutely indispensable, if anything we do is to be
considered our own. unless we are prepared to despair
of moral responsibility altogether, and to resign
ourselves to a comfortless and inexorable necessity.
To make freedom possible, Epicurus had introduced
accident into the motion of atoms, and for the same
reason he denies the truth of disjunctive propositions
which apply to the future. In the latter respect, he,
no doubt, only attacked the material truth of two
clauses, without impugning the formal accuracy of the
disjunction. i.e. he did not deny that of two
contradictory cases either one or the other must
happen, nor did he deny the truth of saying: Tomorrow
Epicurus will either be alive or not alive. But he
disputed the truth of each clause taken by itself. He
denied the truth of the sentence. Epicurus will be
alive; and equally that of its contradictory, Epicurus
will not be alive; on the ground that the one or the
other statement only becomes true by the actual
realization of an event at present uncertain. For this
he deserves little blame. Our real charge against him
is that he did not more thoroughly investigate the
nature of the will and the conception of freedom, and
that he treats the subject of the soul as scantily and
superficially as he had treated the subject of nature.
Chapter XVIII. Views of Epicurus on Religion.
SATISFIED with the results of his own
inquiries into nature. Epicurus hoped by his view of
the causes of things not only to displace the
superstitions of a polytheistic worship, but also to
uproot the prejudice in favor of Providence. Indeed,
these two objects were placed by him on exactly the
same footing. So absurd did he consider the popular
notions respecting the Gods, that instead of blaming
those who attacked them, he believed it impious to
acquiesce in them. Religion being, according to
Lucretius, the cause of the greatest evils, he who
displaces it to make way for rational views of nature
deserves praise as having overcome the most dangerous
enemy of mankind. All the language of Epicurus in
disparagement of the art of poetry applies in a still
higher degree to the religious errors fostered by
poetry. Nor is it better with belief in Providence
than with the popular faith. This belief is also
included in the category of romance; and the doctrine
of fatalism, which was the Stoic form for the same
belief, was denounced as even worse than the popular
faith. For how, asks the Epicurean, could divine
Providence have created a world in which evil abounds,
in which virtue often fares ill, whilst vice is
triumphant? How could a world have been made for the
sake of man, when man can only inhabit a very small
portion of it? How could nature be intended to promote
man’s well-being when it so often imperils his life
and labor, and sends him into the world more helpless
than any animal? How can we form a conception of
beings ruling over an infinite universe, and
everywhere present to administer everything in every
place? What could have induced these beings to create
a world, and how and whence could they have known how
to create it, had not nature supplied them with an
example? In fine, how could God be the happy Being He
must be if the whole burden of caring for all things
and all events lay upon Him, or He were swayed to and
fro together with the body of the world? Or how could
we feel any other feeling than that, of fear in the
presence of such a God who troubles himself about
everything?'
With the denial of the popular Gods, the denial of
demons, of course, goes hand in hand; and, together
with Providence, the need of prayer and of prophecy is
at the same time negatived. All these notions,
according to Epicurus, are the result of ignorance and
fear. Pictures seen in dreams have been confounded
with real existences; regularity of motion in the
heavenly bodies has been mistaken by the ignorant for
the work of God; events which accidentally happened in
combination with others have been regarded as
portents; terrific natural phenomena, storms and
earthquakes, have engendered in men's minds the fear
of higher powers. Fear is therefore the basis of
religion; and, on the other hand, freedom from fear is
the primary object aimed at by philosophy.
For all that, Epicurus was unwilling to renounce
belief in the Gods, nor is it credible that this
unwillingness was simply a yielding to popular
opinion. The language used by the Epicureans certainly
gives the impression of sincerity; and the time was
past when avowed atheism was attended with danger.
Atheism would have been as readily condoned in the
time of Epicurus as the deism which denied most
unreservedly the popular faith. It is, however,
possible to trace the causes which led Epicurus to
believe that there are Gods. There was first the
general diffusion of a belief in Gods which appeared
to him to establish the truth of this belief, and
hence he declared the existence of Gods to be
something directly certain, and grounded on a primary
notion. Moreover, with his materialistic theory of
knowledge he no doubt supposed that the primary notion
which convinces us of the existence of Gods arises
from the actual contemplation of divine beings, and
from the perception of those atom-pictures from which
Democritus had already deduced the belief in Gods. And
in addition to these theoretical reasons, Epicurus had
also another, half aesthetical, half religious--the
wish to see his ideal of happiness realized in the
person of the Gods, and it is this ideal which
determines the character of all his notions respecting
them. His Gods are therefore, throughout, human
beings. Religious belief only knows beings such as
these, or, as Epicurus expresses it, only such beings
come before us in those pictures of the Gods which
present themselves to our minds, sometimes in sleep,
sometimes when we are awake. Reflection, too,
convinces us that the human form is the most
beautiful, that to it alone reason belongs, and that
it is the most appropriate form for perfectly happy
beings. Epicurus even went so far as to attribute to
the Gods difference of sex At the same time everything
must be eliminated which is not appropriate to a
divine being.
The two essential characteristics of the Gods,
according to Epicurus, are immortality and perfect
happiness. Both of these characteristics would be
impaired were we to attribute to the bodies of the
Gods the same dense corporeity which belongs to our
own. We must, therefore, only assign to them a body
analogous to our body, ethereal, and consisting of the
finest atoms. Such bodies would be of little use in a
world like ours. In fact, they could not live in any
world without being exposed to the temporal ruin which
will in time overwhelm it, and, meantime, to a state
of fear, which would mar their bliss. Epicurus,
therefore, assigns the space between the worlds for
their habitation, where, as Lucretius remarks,
troubled by no storms, they live under a sky ever
serene.
Nor can these Gods be supposed to care for the world
and the affairs of men, else their happiness would be
marred by the most distressing occupation; but
perfectly free from care and trouble, and absolutely
regardless of the world, in eternal contemplation of
their unchanging perfection, they enjoy the most
unalloyed happiness. The view which the School formed
to itself of this happiness we learn from Philodemus.
The Gods are exempt from sleep, sleep being a partial
death, and not needed by beings who live without any
exertion. And yet he believes that they require
nourishment, though this must, of course, be of a kind
suited to their nature. They also need dwellings,
since every being requires some place wherein to
dwell. Were powers of speech to be refused to them,
they would be deprived of the highest means of
enjoyment--the power of conversing with their equals.
Philodemus thinks it probable they use the Greek or
some other closely allied language. In short, he
imagines the Gods to be a society of Epicurean
philosophers, who have everything that they can
desire--everlasting life, no care, and perpetual
opportunities of sweet converse. Only such Gods,--the
Epicureans thought,--need not be feared. Only such
Gods are free and pure, and worshipped because of this
very perfection. Moreover, these Gods are innumerable.
If the number of mortal beings is infinite, the law of
counterpoise requires that the number of immortal
beings must not be less. If we have only the idea of a
limited number of Gods, it is because, owing to their
being so much alike, we confound in our minds the
innumerable pictures of the Gods which are conveyed to
our souls.
Priding themselves, in contrast to the Stoics, on
their agreement by means of this theology with the
anthropomorphic views of the popular belief, and even
outdoing polytheism in the assumption of innumerable
Gods, the Epicureans were willing to join in the
customary services of religion, without being nearly
so anxious as the Stoics to prove themselves in
harmony with the popular creed. Whilst the Stoics in
their anxiety to do this had plunged head over heels
into allegory, no such tendency is observed on the
part of the Epicureans. Only the poet of the School
gives a few allegorical interpretations of mythical
ideas, and he does it with more taste and skill than
is usual with the Stoics. On other points the
Epicureans, not excluding Lucretius, observe towards
the popular faith a negative attitude, that of
opposing it by explanations; and by this attitude,
without doubt, they rendered one of the most important
services to humanity.
Chapter XIX. The Moral Science of the Epicureans.
General Principles.
NATURAL science is intended to overcome the prejudices
which stand in the way of happiness; moral science to
give positive instruction as to the nature and means
of attaining to happiness. The speculative parts of
the Epicurean system had already worked out the idea
that reality belongs only to individual things, and
that all general order must be referred to the
accidental harmony of individual forces. The same idea
is now met within the sphere of morals, individual
feeling being made the standard, and individual
well-being the object of all human activity. Natural
science, beginning with external phenomena, went back
to the secret principles of these phenomena,
accessible only to thought. It led from an apparently
accidental movement of atoms to a universe of regular
motions. Not otherwise was the course followed by
Epicurus in moral science. Not content with human
feelings alone, nor with selfishly referring
everything to the individual taken by himself alone,
that science, in more accurately defining the
conception of well-being, ascertained that the same
can only be found by rising superior to feelings and
purely individual aims, in short by that very process
of referring consciousness to itself and its universal
being, which the Stoics declared to be the only path
to happiness. It is for us now to portray this
development of the Epicurean philosophy in its most
prominent features.
The only unconditional good, according to Epicurus, is
pleasure; the only unconditional evil is pain. No
proof of this proposition seemed to him to be
necessary; it rests on a conviction supplied by nature
herself, and is the ground and basis of all our doing
and not doing. If proof, however, were required, he
appealed to the fact that all living beings from the
first moment of their existence pursue pleasure and
avoid pain, and that consequently pleasure is a
natural good, and the normal condition of every being.
Hence follows the proposition to which Epicurus in
common with all the philosophers of pleasure appealed,
that pleasure must be the object of life.
At the same time, this proposition was restricted in
the Epicurean system by several considerations. In the
first place, neither pleasure nor pain is a simple
thing. There are many varieties and degrees of
pleasure and pain, and the case may occur in which
pleasure has to be secured by the loss of other
pleasures, or even by pain, or in which pain can only
be avoided by submitting to another pain, or at the
cost of some pleasure. In this case Epicurus would
have the various feelings of pleasure and pain
carefully weighed, and in consideration of the
advantages and disadvantages which they confer, would
under circumstances advise the good to be treated as
an evil, and the evil as a good. He would have
pleasure forsworn if it would entail a greater
corresponding pain, and pain submitted to if it holds
out the prospect of greater pleasure. He also agrees
with Plato in holding that every positive pleasure
presupposes a want, i.e. a pain which it proposes to
remove; and hence he concludes that the real aim and
object of all pleasure consists in obtaining freedom
from pain, and that the good is nothing else but
emancipation from evil. By a Cyrenaic neither repose
of soul nor freedom from pain, but a gentle motion of
the soul or positive pleasure was proposed as the
object of life; and hence happiness was not made to
depend on man's general state of mind, but on the
sum-total of his actual enjoyments. But Epicurus,
advancing beyond this position, recognized both the
positive and the negative side of pleasures, both
pleasure as repose, and pleasure as motion. Both
aspects of pleasure, however, do not stand on the same
footing in his system. On the contrary, the essential
and immediate cause of happiness is repose of
mind--ataraxia. Positive pleasure is only an indirect
cause of ataraxia in that it removes the pain of
unsatisfied craving. This mental repose, however,
depends essentially on the character of a man’s mind,
just as conversely positive pleasure in systems so
materialistic must depend on sensuous attractions. It
was consistent, therefore, on the part of Aristippus
to consider bodily gratification the highest pleasure;
and conversely Epicurus was no less consistent in
subordinating it to gratification of mind.
In calling pleasure the highest object in life, says
Epicurus, we do not mean the pleasures of profligacy,
nor indeed sensual enjoyments at all, but the freedom
of the body from pain, and the freedom of the soul
from disturbance. Neither feasts nor banquets, neither
the lawful nor unlawful indulgence of the passions,
nor the joys of the table, make life happy, but a
sober judgment, investigating the motives for action
and for inaction, and dispelling those greatest
enemies of our peace, prejudices. The root from which
it springs, and, therefore, the highest good, is
intelligence. It is intelligence that leaves us free
to acquire possession thereof, without being ever too
early or too late. Our indispensable wants are simple,
little being necessary to ensure freedom from pain;
other things only afford change in enjoyment, by which
the quantity is not increased, or else they rest on a
mere sentiment. The little we need may be easily
attained. Nature makes ample provision for our
happiness, would we only receive her gifts thankfully,
not forgetting what she gives in thinking what we
desire. He who lives according to nature is never
poor; the wise man living on bread and water has no
reason to envy Zeus; chance has little hold on him;
with him judgment is everything, and if that be right,
he need trouble himself but little about external
mishaps. Not even bodily pain appeared to Epicurus so
irresistible as to be able to cloud the wise man’s
happiness. Although he regards as unnatural the
Stoic’s insensibility to pain, still he is of opinion
that the wise man may be happy on the rack, and can
smile at pains the most violent, exclaiming in the
midst of torture, How sweet! A touch of forced
sentiment may be discerned in the last expression, and
a trace of self-satisfied exaggeration is manifest
even in the beautiful language of the dying
philosopher on the pains of disease. Nevertheless, the
principle involved is based in the spirit of the
Epicurean philosophy, and borne out by the testimony
of the founder. The main thing, according to Epicurus,
is not the state of the body, but the state of the
mind; bodily pleasure being of short duration, and
having much about it to unsettle: mental enjoyments
only being pure and incorruptible. For the same reason
mental sufferings are more severe than those of the
body, since the body only suffers from present ills,
whilst the soul feels those past and those to come. In
a life of limited duration the pleasures of the flesh
never attain their consummation. Mind only, by
consoling us for the limited nature of our bodily
existence, can produce a life complete in itself, and
not standing in need of unlimited duration.
At the same time, the Epicureans, if consistent with
their principles, could not deny that bodily pleasure
is the earlier form, and likewise the ultimate source,
of all pleasure, and neither Epicurus nor his favorite
pupil Metrodorus shrank from making this admission;
Epicurus declaring that he could form no conception of
the good apart from enjoyments of the senses;
Metrodorus asserting that everything good has
reference to the belly. For all that the Epicureans
did not feel themselves driven to give up the
pre-eminence which they claimed for goods of the soul
over those of the body. Did even the Stoics,
notwithstanding the grossness of their theory of
knowledge, ever abate their demand for a knowledge of
conceptions: or cease to subordinate the senses to
reason, although they built their theory of morals on
nature? But all definite character has vanished from
these intellectual joys and pains. The only
distinctive feature which they possess is the addition
either of memory, or of hope, or of fear to the
present feeling of pleasure or pain; and their greater
importance is simply ascribed to the greater force or
duration belonging to ideal feelings as compared with
the attractions which momentarily impress the senses.
Incidentally the remembrance of philosophic discourses
is mentioned as a counterpoise to bodily pain;
properly speaking, mental pleasures and pains are not
different from other pleasures in kind, but only in
degree, by reason of their being stronger and more
enduring. Accordingly Epicurus cannot escape the
admission that we have no cause for rejecting gross
and carnal enjoyments if these can liberate us from
the fear of higher powers, of death, and of
sufferings; and thus the only consolation he can offer
in pain is the uncertain one that the most violent
pains either do not last long, or else put an end to
life; and the less violent ones ought to be endured
since they do not exclude a counterbalancing pleasure.
Hence victory over the impression of the moment must
be won, not so much by mental force stemming the tide
of feeling, as by a proper estimate of the conditions
and actions of the senses.
In no other way can the necessity of virtue be
established in the Epicurean system. Agreeing with the
strictest moralists, so far as to hold that virtue can
be as little separated from happiness as happiness
from virtue, having even the testimony of opponents as
to the purity and integrity of his moral teaching,
which in its results differed in no wise from that of
the Stoics; Epicurus, nevertheless, holds a position
of strong contrast to the Stoics in respect of the
grounds on which his moral theory is based. To demand
virtue for its own sake seemed to him a mere phantom
of the imagination. Those only who make pleasure their
aim have a real object in life. Virtue has only a
conditional value as a means to happiness; or, as it
is otherwise expressed, Virtue taken by itself does
not render a man happy, but the pleasure arising from
the exercise of virtue. This pleasure the Epicurean
system does not seek in the consciousness of duty
fulfilled, or of virtuous action, but in the freedom
from disquiet, fear, and dangers, which follows as a
consequence from virtue. Wisdom and intelligence
contribute to happiness by liberating us from the fear
of the Gods and of death, by making us independent of
immoderate passions and vain desires, by teaching us
to bear pain as something subordinate and passing, and
by pointing the way to a more cheerful and natural
life. Self-control aids, in that it points out the
attitude to be assumed towards pleasure and pain, so
as to receive the maximum of enjoyment and the minimum
of suffering; valor, in that it enables us to overcome
fear and pain; justice, in that it makes life possible
without that fear of Gods and men, which ever haunts
the transgressor. To the Epicurean virtue is never an
end in itself, but only a means to an end lying
beyond--a happy life--but withal a means so certain
and necessary, that virtue can neither be conceived
without happiness, nor happiness without virtue.
However unnecessary it may seem, still Epicurus would
ever insist that an action to be right must be done
not according to the letter, but according to the
spirit of the law, not simply from regard to others,
or by compulsion, but from delight in what is good.
The same claims were advanced by Epicurus on behalf of
his wise man as the Stoics had urged on behalf of
theirs. Not only does he attribute to him a control
over pain, in nothing inferior to the Stoic
insensibility of feeling, but he endeavors himself to
describe the wise man’s life as most perfect and
satisfactory in itself. Albeit not free from emotions,
and in particular susceptible to the higher feelings
of the soul such as compassion, the wise man finds his
philosophic activity in no wise thereby impaired.
Without despising enjoyment, he is altogether master
of his desires, and knows how to restrain them by
intelligence, so that they never exercise a harmful
influence on life. He alone has an unwavering
certainty of conviction; he alone knows how to do the
right thing in the right way; he alone, as Metrodorus
observes, knows how to be thankful. Nay, more, he is
so far exalted above ordinary men, that Epicurus
promises his pupils that, by carefully observing his
teaching, they will dwell as Gods among men; so little
can destiny influence him, that he calls him happy
under all circumstances. Happiness may, indeed, depend
on certain external conditions; it may even be allowed
that the disposition to happiness is not found in
every nature, nor in every person; but still, when it
is found, its stability is sure, nor can time affect
its duration. For wisdom--so Epicurus and the Stoics
alike believed--is indestructible, and the wise man’s
happiness can never be increased by time. A life,
therefore, bounded by time can be quite as complete as
one not so bounded.
Different as are the principles and the tone of the
systems of the Stoics and of Epicurus, one and the
same tendency may yet be traced in both--the tendency
which characterizes all the post-Aristotelian
philosophy--the desire to place man in a position of
absolute independence by emancipating him from
connection with the external world, and by awakening
in him the consciousness of the infinite freedom of
thought.
Chapter XX. The Epicurean Ethics Continued: Special
Points.
THE general principles already laid down
determine likewise the character of particular points
in the moral science of the Epicureans. Epicurus, it
is true, never developed his moral views to a
systematic theory of moral actions and states, however
much his pupils, particularly in later times, busied
themselves with morality and special points in a
system of morals. Moreover, his fragmentary statements
and precepts are very imperfectly recorded. Still, all
that is known corresponds with the notion which we
must form in accordance with those general views. All
the practical rules given by Epicurus aim at
conducting man to happiness by controlling passions
and desires. The wise man is easily satisfied. He sees
that little is necessary for supplying the wants of
nature, and for emancipating from pain; that imaginary
wealth knows no limit, whereas the riches required by
nature may be easily acquired; that the most simple
nourishment affords as much enjoyment as the most
luxurious, and is at the same time far more conducive
to health; that therefore the restriction of wants
rather than the increase of possessions makes really
rich; and that he who is not satisfied with little
will never be satisfied at all. He therefore can like
Epicurus live upon bread and water, and at the same
time think himself as happy as Zeus. He eschews
passions which disturb peace of mind and the repose of
life; considering it foolish to throw away the present
in order to obtain an uncertain future, or to
sacrifice life itself for the means of life, seeing he
can only once enjoy it. He therefore neither gives way
to passionate love, nor to forbidden acts of
profligacy. Fame he does not covet; and for the
opinions of men he cares only so far as to wish not to
be despised, since being despised would expose him to
danger. Injuries he can bear with calmness. He cares
not what may happen to him after death; nor envies any
one the possessions which he does not himself value.
It has been already seen how Epicurus thought to rise
above pains, and to emancipate himself from the fear
of the Gods and death. And it has been further noticed
that he thinks to secure by means of his principles
the same independence and happiness which the Stoics
aspired to by means of theirs. But whilst the Stoics
hoped to attain this independence by crushing the
senses, Epicurus was content to restrain and regulate
them. Desires he would not have uprooted, but he would
have them brought into proper proportion to the
collective end and condition of life, into the
equilibrium necessary for perfect repose of mind.
Hence, notwithstanding his own simplicity, Epicurus is
far from disapproving, under all circumstances, of a
fuller enjoyment of life. The wise man will not live
as a Cynic or a beggar. Care for business he will not
neglect; only he will not trouble himself too much
about it, and will prefer the business of education to
any and every other. Nor will he despise the
attractions of art, although he is satisfied when
obliged to do without them. In short, his
self-sufficiency will not consist in using
little, but in needing little; and it is this
freedom from wants which adds flavor to his more
luxurious enjoyments. His attitude to death is the
same. Not fearing death, rather seeking it when he has
no other mode of escaping unendurable suffering, he
will resort to suicide if necessary, but the cases
will be rare, because he has learned to be happy under
all bodily pains. The Stoic’s recommendation of
suicide finds no favor with him.
However self-sufficing the wise man may be, still
Epicurus will not separate him from connection with
others. Not, indeed, that he believed with the Stoics
in the natural relationship of all rational beings.
Yet even he could form no idea of human life except in
connection with human society. He does not, however,
assign the same value to all forms of social life.
Civil society and the state have for him the least
attraction. Civil society is only an external
association for the purpose of protection. Justice
reposes originally on a contract entered into for
purposes of mutual security. Laws are made for the
sake of the wise, not to prevent their committing, but
to prevent their suffering injustice. Law and justice
are not, therefore, binding for their own sake, but
for the general good; nor is injustice to be condemned
for its own sake, but only because the offender can
never be free from fear of discovery and punishment.
There is not, therefore, any such thing as universal,
unchangeable justice. The claims of justice only
extend to a limited number of beings and
nations--those, in fact, which are able and willing to
enter into the social compact. And the particular
applications of justice which constitute positive
right differ in different cases, and change with
circumstances. What is felt to be conducive to mutual
security must pass for justice, and whenever a law is
seen to be inexpedient it is no longer binding. The
wise man will therefore only enter into political life
in case and in as far as this is necessary for his own
safety. Sovereign power is a good, inasmuch as it
protects from harm. He who pursues it, without thereby
attaining this object, acts most foolishly. Since
private individuals live as a rule much more quietly
and safely than statesmen, it was natural that the
Epicureans should be averse to public affairs; public
life, after all, is a hindrance to what is the real
end-in-chief--wisdom and happiness. Their watchword
is Live unknown. To them the golden mean
seemed by far the most desirable lot in life. They
only advise citizens to take part in public affairs
when special circumstances render it necessary, or
when an individual has such a restless nature that he
cannot be content with the quiet of private life.
Otherwise they are too deeply convinced of the
impossibility of pleasing the masses to wish even to
make the attempt. For the same reason they appear to
have been partisans of monarchy. The stern and
unflinching moral teaching of the Stoics had found its
political expression in the unbending republican
spirit, so often encountered at Rome. Naturally the
soft and timid spirit of the Epicureans took shelter
under a monarchical constitution. Of their political
principles one thing at least is known, that they did
not consider it degrading for a wise man to pay court
to princes, and under all circumstances they
recommended unconditional obedience to the powers that
be.
Family life is said to have been deprecated by
Epicurus equally with civil life. Stated thus baldly,
this is an exaggeration. It appears, however, to be
established, that Epicurus believed it to be generally
better for the wise man to forego marriage and the
rearing of children, since he would thereby save
himself many disturbances. It is also quite credible
that he declared the love of children towards parents
to be no inborn feeling. This view is, after all, only
a legitimate consequence of his materialism; but it
did not oblige him to give up parental love
altogether. Nay, it is asserted of him that he was
anything but a stranger to family affections.
The highest form of social life was considered by
Epicurus to be friendship--a view which is peculiar in
a system that regarded the individual as the atom of
society. Such a system naturally attributes more value
to a connection with others freely entered upon and
based on individual character and personal
inclination, than to one in which a man finds himself
placed without any choice, as a member of a society
founded on nature or history. The basis, however, on
which the Epicurean friendship rests is very
superficial; regard is mainly had to its advantages,
and in some degree to the natural effects of common
enjoyments; but it is also treated in such a way, that
its scientific imperfection has no influence on its
moral importance. Only one section of the School, and
that not the most consistent, maintained that
friendship is pursued in the first instance for the
sake of its own use and pleasure, but that it
subsequently becomes an unselfish love. The assumption
that among the wise there exists a tacit agreement
requiring them to love one another as much as they
love themselves, is clearly only a lame shift. Still,
the Epicureans were of opinion that a grounding of
friendship on motives of utility was not inconsistent
with holding it in the highest esteem. Friendly
connection with others affords so pleasant a feeling
of security, that it entails the most enjoyable
consequences; and since this connection can only exist
when friends love one another as themselves, it
follows that self-love and the love of a friend must
be equally strong.
Even this inference sounds forced, nor does it fully
state the grounds on which Epicurus’s view of the
value of friendship reposes. That view, in fact, was
anterior to all the necessary props of the system.
What Epicurus requires is primarily enjoyment. The
first conditions of such enjoyment, however, are
inward repose of mind, and the removal of fear of
disturbances. But Epicurus was far too effeminate and
dependent on externals to trust his own powers to
satisfy these conditions. He needed the support of
others, not only to obtain their help in necessity and
trouble, and to console himself for the uncertainty of
the future, but still more, to make sure of himself
and his principles by having the approval of others,
and thus obtaining an inward satisfaction which he
could not otherwise have had. Thus, the approval of
friends is to him the pledge of the truth of his
convictions. In sympathy with friends his mind first
attains to a strength by which it is able to rise
above the changing circumstances of life. General
ideas are for him too abstract, too unreal. A
philosopher who considers individual beings as alone
real, and perceptions as absolutely true, cannot feel
quite happy and sure of his ground, unless he finds
others to go with him. The enjoyment which he seeks is
the enjoyment of his own cultivated personality; and
wherever this standard prevails, particular value is
attached to the personal relations of society, and to
friendship.
Hence Epicurus uses language on the value and
necessity of friendship which goes far beyond the
grounds on which he bases it. Friendship is
unconditionally the highest of earthly goods. It is
far more important in whose company we eat and drink,
than what we eat and drink. In case of emergency, the
wise man will not shrink from suffering the greatest
pains, even death, for his friend.
It is well known that the conduct of Epicurus and his
followers was in harmony with these professions. The
Epicurean friendship is hardly less celebrated than
the Pythagorean. There may be an offensive mawkishness
and a tendency to mutual admiration apparent in the
relations of Epicurus to his friends, but of the
sincerity of his feelings there can be no doubt. One
single expression referring to the property of
friends, is enough to prove what a high view Epicurus
held of friendship; and there is evidence to show that
he aimed at a higher improvement of his associates.
In other respects Epicurus bore the reputation of
being a kind, benevolent, and genial companion. His
teaching bears the same impress. It meets the
inexorable sternness of the Stoics by insisting on
compassion and forgiveness, and supersedes its own
egotism by the maxim that it is more blessed to give
than to receive. The number of such maxims on record
is, no doubt, limited; nevertheless, the whole tone of
the Epicurean School is a pledge of the humane and
generous character of its moral teaching. To this
trait that School owes its chief importance in
history. By its theory of utility it undoubtedly did
much harm, partly exposing, partly helping forward,
the moral decline of the classic nations. Still, by
drawing man away from the outer world within himself,
by teaching him to seek happiness in the beautiful
type of a cultivated mind content with itself, it
contributed quite as much as Stoicism, though after a
gentler fashion, to the development and the extension
of a more independent and more universal morality.
Chapter XXI. The Epicurean System as a Whole; Its
Position in History.
IT has often been urged against the Epicurean
philosophy, that it is deficient both in coherence and
consistency. Nor is this objection without foundation.
If we come to the study of it, looking for a complete
scientific groundwork, or a strictly logical
development, we shall certainly be disappointed. It is
not difficult to show in what contradictions Epicurus
was involved; in professing to trust the senses wholly
and entirely, and yet going beyond the senses to the
hidden causes of things; in despising logical forms
and laws, and at the same time building up his whole
system on deductions; in holding that all sensations
are true, but yet maintaining that a portion of the
realities which they represent as belonging to things
is only relative. Nor were these the only
inconsistencies. At one time only natural causes and
laws are acknowledged, and any such thing as free will
and imagination is ignored; at another, by the
doctrine of the swerving aside of atoms and of the
human will, unexplained caprice is elevated to the
rank of law. Pleasures and pains are all referred to
bodily sensations, and yet mental states are called
higher and more important; nay, more, even from a
basis of selfishness rules and precepts of humanity,
justice, love, faithfulness, and devotion are deduced.
It ought not, however, to be forgotten that the
Stoics, to whom the claim of clear and consistent
thought cannot be denied, were involved in similar
difficulties. They, like the Epicureans, built up a
rational system on a basis of the senses. They, too,
constructed an ideal theory of morals on a material
groundwork of metaphysics. They, too, declared that
universal law is the only active power, whilst they
maintained that reality belongs only to the world of
matter. They, too, deduced a strict theory of virtue
from the principle of self-preservation; not to
mention the inconsistent attitude which they assumed
towards the popular religion. To deny to the Stoics a
unity and connectedness of system, because of these
scientific defects and inconsistencies, would be felt
to be doing them an injustice. And can Epicureanism be
fairly condemned, when its faults are essentially of
the same kind (though a little more obvious) as those
of the Stoics, without a single extenuating
circumstance which can be urged on its behalf?
The strongest argument in favor of Epicureanism is
that the development of the system does not pretend to
rest upon an intellectual platform. Epicurus sought in
philosophy a path to happiness, a school of practical
wisdom. For him knowledge has only a secondary value,
because it contributes to this end; indeed, both the
tone and the results of his intellectual activity were
determined by a reference to this end. In the case of
the Stoics, however, it has been already seen that the
comparative subordination of Logic and Natural Science
to Moral Science, the going back to the older view of
nature, the vindication of the truth of the senses and
of the reality of matter, grew out of their peculiarly
one-sided view of the scope of philosophy. In the
case of Epicurus the same results appear, and all the
more markedly, since Epicurus did not, like the
Stoics, look for happiness in subordination to a
universal law, but in individual gratification or
pleasure. For him the recognition of a universal law
had not the same importance as for the Stoics; and
consequently Epicurus did not feel the same need of a
scientific method as they had done. He could therefore
more exclusively content himself with the impressions
of the senses, and regard them as the only unfailing
source of knowledge. No necessity compelled him to
advance from pure materialism to a view of matter in
which it is described as possessing a soul, and made
to be the bearer of reason. In fact, the more
exclusively everything was referred by him to
mechanical causes, the more easily could he regard the
individual as independent of all superhuman forces in
his pursuit of happiness, and left entirely to himself
and his natural powers. No system in ancient times has
so consistently carried out the mechanical view of
nature as that of the Atomists. None, therefore,
afforded such a strong metaphysical support to the
Epicurean views of the absolute worth of the
individual. It was as natural for Epicurus to build on
the teaching of Democritus as for the Stoics to build
on that of Heraclitus. But Epicurus, influenced
probably more by practical than by scientific
considerations, allowed himself, by his theory of the
swerving aside of atoms, to destroy the consistency of
the theory of Democritus.
It is hardly necessary to notice here how the
distinctive features of the Epicurean morals were
developed out of their theory of happiness, in
contrast to the Stoic teaching. The happiness of
Epicurus, however, does not depend upon sensual
gratification as such, but upon repose of mind and
cheerfulness of disposition. His theory of morals,
therefore, notwithstanding its foundation in pleasure,
bears a nobler character, which is seen in its
language as to the wise man’s relations to the pains
and passions of the body, to poverty and riches, to
life and death, quite as much as in the mild humanity
and the warm and hearty appreciation of friendship by
the Epicurean School. The rationalizing spirit of that
School was undoubtedly opposed to any religious belief
which supposed an intervention of God in the course of
the world, or the world's influence on man for weal or
woe; but its appeal to the senses without criticism
placed no objection in the way of admitting divine
beings, from whom no such intervention need be feared.
Nay, more, this belief seemed the most natural ground
for explaining the popular belief in Gods. It
satisfied an inborn and apparently keenly felt want by
supplying an appropriate object of devotion, and a
standard by which to test the accuracy of moral ideas.
Hence, notwithstanding scientific defects and
contradictions, the whole system of Epicurus bears a
definite stamp. All the essential parts of that system
are subservient to one and the same end. The
consistent working out of a scientific view of nature
is looked for in vain; but there is no lack of
consistency arising from an undeniable reference of
the individual to a definite and practical standard.
Looking to the wider historical relations of the
Epicurean system, the first point which calls for
remark is the relation of that system to Stoicism. The
contrast between the two Schools is obvious; attention
having been already drawn to it on all the important
points, it is likewise well known that a constant
rivalry existed between the two Schools during their
whole careers, that the Stoics looked down on the
Epicureans, and circulated many calumnies with respect
to their morals. For these statements proofs may be
found in the preceding pages. Nevertheless, the two
Schools are related in so many respects, that they can
only be regarded as parallel links connected in one
chain, their differences being varieties where the
same main tendency exists. Both agree in the general
character of their philosophy. In both practical
considerations prevail over speculation. Both treat
natural science and logic as sciences subsidiary to
ethics--natural science especially in view of its
bearing on religion. Both attach more importance to
natural science than to logic. If the Epicurean
neglect of scientific rules forms a contrast to the
care which the Stoics devoted thereto, both Schools
are at least agreed in one thing--in displaying
greater independence in investigating the question as
to a test of truth. By both this standard was placed
in the senses; and to all appearances both were led to
take this view by the same cause; appeals to the
senses being a consequence of their purely practical
way of looking at things. Both, moreover, employed
against skepticism the same practical postulate--the
argument that knowledge must be possible, or no
certainty of action would be possible. They even agree
in not being content with the phenomena supplied by
the senses as such, although Epicurus as little
approved of the Stoic theory of irresistible
impressions as he did of their logical analysis of the
forms of thought. With such appeals to the senses how
could there be any other result than materialism both
in the Stoic and Epicurean systems? But it is strange
that the materialism in both Schools should be based
on the same definition of reality, corresponding with
their practical way of looking at things.
In the unfolding and detailed exposition of their
materialistic views the systems diverge, more widely,
perhaps, than the philosophers themselves, whose
leading they professed to follow. These divergencies
appear particularly on the subject of nature, the
Stoics regarding nature as a system of design, the
Epicureans explaining it as a mechanical product.
Whilst the Stoics adhered to fatalism, and saw God
everywhere, the Epicureans held the theory of atoms,
and the theory of necessity. Whilst the Stoics were
speculatively orthodox, the Epicureans were
irreligious freethinkers. Both meet again in that
branch of natural science which is most important in
respect of morals--the part dealing with man. Both
hold that the soul is a fiery atmospheric substance.
Even the proof for this view, derived from the mutual
influence of body and soul, is common to both. Both
distinguish between the higher and the lower parts of
the soul, and thus even the Epicureans in their
psychology allow a belief in the superiority of reason
to the senses, and in the divine origin of the soul.
The arena of the warmest dispute between the two
Schools is, however, ethics. Yet, even on this ground,
they are more nearly related than appears at first
sight. No greater contrast appears to be possible than
that between the Epicurean theory of pleasure and the
Stoic theory of virtue; and true it is that the two
theories are diametrically opposite. Nevertheless, not
only are both aiming at one and the same end--the
happiness of mankind--but the conditions of happiness
are also laid down by both in the same spirit.
According to Zeno virtue, according to Epicurus
pleasure, is the highest and only good; but the former
in making virtue consist essentially in withdrawal
from the senses or insensibility; the latter in
seeking pleasure in repose of mind or
imperturbability, are expressing the same belief. Man
can only find unconditional and enduring satisfaction,
when by means of knowledge he attains to a condition
of mind at rest with itself, and also to an
independence of external attractions and misfortunes.
The same unlimited appeal to personal truth is the
common groundwork of both systems. Both have expanded
this idea under the same form--that of the ideal wise
man--for the most part with the same features. The
wise man of Epicurus is, as we have seen, superior to
pain and want; he enjoys an excellence which cannot be
lost; and he lives among men a very God in
intelligence and happiness. Thus, when worked out into
details, the difference in the estimate of pleasure
and virtue by the Stoics and Epicureans seems to
vanish. Neither the Stoic can separate happiness from
virtue, nor the Epicurean separate virtue from
happiness.
But, whilst recommending a living for society, both
systems take no real interest in social life. The
recognition of a natural society amongst mankind, of
certain positive relations to state and family, above
all, a clear enunciation of a citizenship of the
world, characterize the Stoics. The pursuit of
friendship, and the gentle humanity of their ethics,
characterize the Epicureans. Together with these
peculiarities one common feature cannot be ignored.
Both have renounced the political character of the old
propriety of conduct, and diverting their attention
from public life, seek to find a basis for universal
morality in the simple relation of man to man.
The united weight of all these points of resemblance
is sufficient to warrant the assertion that,
notwithstanding their differences, the Stoics and
Epicureans stand on the same footing, and that the
sharpness of the contrast between them is owing to
their laying hold of opposite sides of one and the
same principle. Abstract personality, and
self-consciousness developed into a generic idea, is
for both the highest aim. Compared with it not only
the state of the senses, but the scientific knowledge
of things, and the realization of moral ideas in a
commonwealth, are of minor importance. In this
self-consciousness happiness consists. To implant it
in man is the object of philosophy, and knowledge is
only of value when and in as far as it ministers to
this end. The point of difference between the two
Schools is their view of the conditions under which
that certainty of consciousness is attained. The
Stoics hope to attain it by the entire subordination
of the individual to universal law. The Epicureans, on
the other hand, are of the opinion that man can only
then be content in himself when he is restrained by
nothing external to himself. The first condition of
happiness consists in liberating individual life from
all dependence on others, and all disturbing causes.
The former, therefore, make virtue, the latter make
personal well-being or pleasure, the highest good. By
the Epicureans, however, pleasure is usually conceived
as of a purely negative character, as being freedom
from pain, and is referred to the whole of human life.
Hence it is always made to depend on the moderation of
desires, on indifference to outward ills, and the
state of the senses, on intelligence and actions
conformable with intelligence, in short, on virtue and
wisdom. Hence, too, the Epicureans arrive by a
roundabout course at the same result as the
Stoics--the conviction that happiness can only be the
lot of those who are altogether independent of
external things, and enjoy perfect inward harmony.
Towards the older philosophy Epicureanism bears nearly
the same relation as Stoicism. True it is that
Epicurus and his School would not recognize their
obligation to either one or other of their
predecessors. But far from disproving the influence of
previous systems on his own, this conduct only shows
the personal vanity of Epicurus. Epicureanism, like
Stoicism, starts with the object of bringing down
science from metaphysical speculation to the simpler
form of a practical science of life. Both systems of
philosophy, therefore, turn away from Plato and
Aristotle, whose labors they notably neglect, to
Socrates and those Socratic Schools which, without
more extensive meddling with science, are content with
ethics. Circumstances, however, led Epicurus to follow
Aristippus as Zeno had followed Antisthenes. Not only
in morals did Epicurus derive his principle of
pleasure from the Cyrenaics; he likewise derived from
them his theory of knowledge, that the
sense-impressions are the only source of ideas, and
that every feeling is true in itself. Nor can he
altogether deny that feelings only furnish direct
information respecting our personal states, and
respecting the relative properties of things. With the
Cyrenaics, too, he taught that true pleasure can only
be secured by philosophic intelligence, and that this
intelligence aims, before all things, at liberating
the mind from passion, fear, and superstition. At the
same time, he is by no means prepared to follow the
Cyrenaics unreservedly. His theory of morals differs,
as has already been seen, from the Cyrenaic theory in
this important particular, that not sensual and
individual pleasure, but mental repose and the whole
state of the mind is regarded as the ultimate end, and
the highest good in life. It was thus impossible for
him to be content, as the Cyrenaics were, with
feelings only, with individual and personal
impressions. He could not help requiring conviction
which reposed on a real knowledge of things, since
only on such conviction can an equable and certain
tone of mind depend.
Epicurus, therefore, not only differed from Aristippus
with regard to feelings, by referring all feelings to
impressions from without, of which he considered them
true representations, but he felt himself called upon
to oppose the Cyrenaic contempt for theories of
nature, just as the Stoics had opposed the Cynic
contempt for science. To the physics of Democritus he
looked for a scientific basis for his ethics, just as
they had looked to the system of Heraclitus. But the
closer he clung to Democritus, owing to the weakness
of his own interest in nature, the more it becomes
apparent that his whole study of nature was
subservient to a moral purpose, and hence of a purely
relative value. Accordingly, he had not the least
hesitation in setting consistency at defiance, by
assuming the swerving aside of atoms and the freedom
of the will. It is not only altogether improbable that
Epicurus was but a second edition of Democritus--for
history knows of no such repetitions--but as a matter
of fact it is false. Closer observation proves that
even when the two philosophers agree in individual
statements, the meaning which they attach to these
assertions and the whole spirit of their systems are
widely divergent. Democritus aims at explaining
natural phenomena by natural causes. He wishes, in
short, for a science of nature purely for its own
sake. Epicurus wishes for a view of nature which shall
be able to avert disturbing influences from man’s
inner life. Natural science stands with him entirely
in the service of ethics. If in point of substance his
system is borrowed from another system, yet its whole
position and treatment supposes an entirely new view
of things. The Socratic introspection, and the
Sophistic resolution of natural philosophy into
personal rationalizing, are its historical
antecedents; and it owes its existence to that general
dislike for pure theory, which constitutes the common
peculiarity of all the post-Aristotelian systems.
Excepting the systems named, Epicureanism, so far as
is known, is connected with no other previous system.
Even its attack upon those systems appears to have
consisted of general dogmatic and superficial
statements. Still it must not be forgotten that
Epicureanism presupposes the line of thought
originated by Socrates, not only as found in the
collateral Cyrenaic branch, but as found in the main
line of regular development by Plato and Aristotle.
The view of Plato and Aristotle, which distinguishes
the immaterial essence from the sensible appearance of
things, and attributes reality only to the former, is
undoubtedly attacked by Epicurus as by Zeno, on
metaphysical grounds. Practically, however, he
approaches very much nearer to this view in all those
points in which his teaching deviates from the
Cyrenaic and resembles that of the Stoics.
It has been observed on a former occasion that the
indifference to the immediate conditions of the
senses, the withdrawal of the mind within itself, the
contentment with itself of the thinking subject, which
Epicurus no less than the Stoics and contemporary
Sceptics required, is itself a consequence of the
idealism of Plato and Aristotle. Even the materialism
of the post-Aristotelian systems, it is said, was by
no means a going back to the old pre-Socratic
philosophy of nature, but a one-sided practical
apprehension of that idealism. These systems deny a
soul in nature or a soul in man, because they look
exclusively to consciousness and to personal activity
for independence of the senses. The correctness of
this observation may be easily proved from the
Epicurean teaching, notwithstanding the severity and
harshness of its materialism. Why was it that Epicurus
relentlessly banished from nature all immaterial
causes and all idea of purpose? And why did he confine
himself exclusively to a mechanical explanation of
nature? Was it not because he felt afraid that the
admission of any other than material causes would
imperil the certainty of consciousness; because he
feared to lose the firm groundwork of reality by
admitting invisible forces, and to expose human life
to influences beyond calculation if he allowed
anything immaterial? Yet in his view of life, how
little does he adhere to present facts, since his wise
man is made to enjoy perfect happiness by himself
alone, independent of everything external. The same
ideal is reproduced in the Epicurean Gods. In their
isolated contemplation of themselves, what else do
they resemble but the God of Aristotle, who, aloof
from all intermeddling with the world, meditates on
himself alone? No doubt the independent existence of
the thinking mind is held by Aristotle in a clear and
dignified manner. By Epicurus it is portrayed in a
sensuous, and, therefore, a contradictory form. But
the connection of the views of both cannot be ignored.
There is a similar general relation between the
Epicurean philosophy and that of Plato and Aristotle.
Little as the former can be compared with the latter
in breadth and depth, it must not, therefore, be
regarded as an intellectual monstrosity. Epicureanism
is a tenable though one-sided expression of a certain
stage in the development of the intellect of Greece.
PART IV. THE SCEPTICS--PYRRHO AND THE OLDER
ACADEMY.
Chapter XXII. Pyrrho.
STOICISM and Epicureanism are alike in one
respect: they commence the pursuit of happiness with
definite dogmatic statements. The Sceptic Schools,
however, attempt to reach the same end by denying
every dogmatic position. Varied as the paths may be,
the result is in all cases the same; happiness is made
to consist in the exaltation of the mind above all
external objects, in the withdrawal of man within his
own thinking self. Moving in the same sphere as the
contemporary dogmatic systems, the post-Aristotelian
Skepticism takes a practical view of the business of
philosophy, and estimates the value of theoretical
inquiries by their influence on the state and
happiness of man. It moreover agrees with contemporary
systems in its ethical view of life; the object at
which it aims is the same as that at which those
systems aim, viz. repose of mind, and
imperturbability. It differs from them, none the less;
for the Epicureans and Stoics made mental repose to
depend on a knowledge of the world and its laws,
whereas the Sceptics are of opinion that it can only
be obtained by despairing of all knowledge. Hence,
with the former morality depends on a positive
conviction as to the highest Good; with the latter,
morality consists in indifference to all that appears
as Good to men. Important as this difference may be,
it must not therefore be forgotten that Skepticism
generally revolves in the same sphere as Stoicism and
Epicureanism, and that in renouncing all claim to
knowledge, and all interest in the external world, it
is only pushing to extremes that withdrawal of man
into himself which we have seen to be the common
feature of these Schools. Not only, therefore, do
these three lines of thought belong to one and the
same epoch, but such is their internal connection that
they may be regarded as three branches of a common
stock.
More than one point of departure was offered to
Skepticism by the earlier philosophy. The Megarian
criticism and the Cynic teaching had taken up a
position subversive of all connection of ideas, and of
all knowledge. Pyrrho, too, had received from the
School of Democritus an impulse to doubt. In
particular, the development of the Platonic and
Aristotelian speculations by those who were not able
to follow them, had made men mistrustful of all
speculation. until they at last doubted the
possibility of all knowledge. Not seldom do Skeptical
theories follow times of great philosophical
originality. A stronger impulse was given in the
sequel by the Stoic and Epicurean systems. Related to
Skepticism by their practical tone, it was natural
that these systems should afford fuel to Skepticism At
the same time the unsatisfactory groundwork upon which
they were built, and the contrast between their moral
and physical teaching, promoted destructive criticism.
If, according to the Stoics and Epicureans, the
particular and the universal elements in the personal
soul, the isolation of the individual as an
independent atom, and his being merged in a
pantheistic universe, are contrasted without being
reconciled; among the Sceptics this contrast has given
place to neutrality. Neither the Stoic nor the
Epicurean theory can claim our adherence; neither the
unconditional value of pleasure, nor yet the
unconditional value of virtue; neither the truth of
the senses nor the truth of rational knowledge;
neither the Atomist’s view of nature, nor the
Pantheistic view as it found expression in Heraclitus.
The only thing which remains certain amid universal
uncertainty is abstract personality content with
itself, personality forming at once the starting-point
and the goal of the two contending systems.
The important back-influence of Stoicism and
Epicureanism upon Skepticism may be best gathered from
the fact that Skepticism only attained a wide
extension and a more comprehensive basis in the New
Academy after the appearance of those systems. Before
that time its leading features had been indeed laid
down by Pyrrho, but they had never been developed into
a permanent School of Skepticism, nor given rise to an
expanded theory of doubt.
Pyrrho was a native of Elis, and may therefore have
early made the acquaintance of the Elean and Megarian
criticism--that criticism, in fact, which was the
precursor of subsequent Skepticism It can, however,
hardly be true that Bryso was his instructor. To
Anaxarchus, a follower of Democritus, he attached
himself, and accompanied that philosopher with
Alexander's army as far as India. Perhaps, however, he
is less indebted to Anaxarchus for the skeptical than
for the ethical parts of his teaching. At a later
period he resided in his native city, honored by his
fellow-citizens, but in poor circumstances, which he
bore with his characteristic repose of mind. He died,
it would appear, at an advanced age, between 275 and
270 B.C., leaving no writings behind. Even the
ancients, therefore, only knew his teaching by that of
his pupils, among whom Timon of Phlius was the most
distinguished. Besides Timon several other of his
pupils are known by name. His School, however, was
short-lived. Soon after Timon it seems to have become
extinct. Those who were disposed to be skeptical now
joined the New Academy, towards whose founder even
Timon made no secret of his grudge.
The little which is known of Pyrrho’s teaching may be
summed up in the three following statements: We can
know nothing as to the nature of things: Hence the
right attitude towards them is to withhold judgment:
The necessary result of suspending judgment is
imperturbability. He who will live happily--for
happiness is the starting-point with the
Sceptics--must, according to Timon, take these things
into consideration: What is the nature of things? What
ought our attitude to things to be? What is the gain
resulting from these relations? To the first of these
three questions Pyrrho can only reply by saying that
things are altogether inaccessible to knowledge, and
that whatever property may be attributed to a thing,
with equal justice the opposite may be predicated. In
support of this statement Pyrrho appears to have
argued that neither the senses nor reason furnish
certain knowledge. The senses do not show things as
they are, but only as they appear to be. Rational
knowledge, even where it seems to be most certain, in
the sphere of morals, does not depend upon real
knowledge, but only upon tradition and habit. Against
every statement the opposite may be advanced with
equal justice. If, however, neither the senses nor
reason alone can furnish trustworthy testimony, no
more can the two combined, and thus the third way is
barred, by which we might possibly have advanced to
knowledge. How many more of the arguments quoted by
the later Sceptics belong to Pyrrho it is impossible
to say. The short duration and diffusion of Pyrrho's
School renders it probable that with him Skepticism
was not far advanced. The same result appears to
follow from its further development in the Academy.
The ten trophes, or aspects under which skeptical
objections were grouped, cannot with certainty be
attributed to any one before Aenesidemus. Portions of
the arguments used at a later day may be borrowed from
Pyrrho and his pupils, but it is impossible to
discriminate these portions with certainty.
Thus, if knowledge of things proves to be a failure,
there only remains as possible an attitude of pure
Skepticism; and therein is contained the answer to the
second question. We know nothing whatever of the real
nature of things, and hence can neither believe nor
assert anything as to their nature. We cannot say of
anything that it is or is not; but we
must abstain from every opinion, allowing that of all
which appears to us to be true, the opposite may with
equal justice be true. Accordingly, all our statements
(as the Cyrenaics taught) only express individual
opinions, and not absolute realities. We cannot deny
that things appear to be of this or the other
kind; but we can never say that they are so. Even the
assertion that things are of this or the other kind is
not an assertion, but a confession by the individual
of his state of mind. Hence, too, the universal rule
of indecision cannot be taken as an established
principle, but only as a confession, and, therefore,
as only problematical. It must, however, remain a
matter of doubt how far the captious turns of
expression by which the Sceptics thought to parry the
attacks of their opponents come from Pyrrho's School.
The greater part, it is clear, came into use in the
struggle with the Dogmatists, and are not older than
the development of the Stoic theory of knowledge by
Chrysippus, and the criticism of Carneades to which it
gave rise. In this despairing of anything like certain
conviction consists speechlessness, incomprehensibleness,
or suspension, the withholding of judgment or
state of indecision which Pyrrho and Timon regard as
the only true attitude in speculation, and from which
the whole School derived its distinctive name.
From this state of indecision, Timon, in reply to the
third question, argues that mental imperturbability or
ataraxia proceeds, which can alone conduct to true
happiness. Men are disturbed by views and prejudices
which mislead them into the efforts of passion. Only
the Sceptic who has suspended all judgment is in a
condition to regard things with absolute calmness,
unruffled by passion or desire. He knows that it is a
fond delusion to suppose that one external condition
is preferable to another. In reality only the tone of
mind or virtue possesses value. Thus, by withdrawing
within himself, man reaches happiness, which is the
goal of all philosophy. Absolute inactivity being,
however, impossible, the Sceptic will act on
probabilities, and hence follow custom; but at the
same time he will be conscious that such conduct does
not rest on a basis of firm conviction. The province
of uncertain opinion includes all positive judgments
respecting good and evil. Only in this conditional
form will Timon allow of goodness and divine goodness
as standards of conduct. The real object of Skepticism
is, therefore, a purely negative one--indifference. It
cannot even be proved that Pyrrho’s School so far
accommodated itself to life, as to make moderation
rather than indifference the regulating principle for
unavoidable actions and desires. In this direction the
School seems to have done but little.
Chapter XXIII. The New Academy.
PLATO'S School was the first to put
Skepticism on a firm footing, and to cultivate it as a
system. It has been already remarked that after the
time of Xenocrates this School gradually deserted
speculative inquiries, and limited itself to Ethics.
To this new tendency it consistently adhered, when,
shortly after the beginning of the third century
before Christ, it took a fresh lease of life. Instead,
however, of simply ignoring theoretical knowledge, as
it had hitherto done, it assumed towards knowledge an
attitude of opposition, hoping to arrive at security
and happiness in life by being persuaded of the
impossibility of knowledge. How far this result was
due to the example set by Pyrrho it is impossible to
establish authoritatively. But it is not in itself
probable that the learned originator of this line of
thought in the Academy should have ignored the views
of a philosopher whose work had been carried on at
Elis in his own lifetime, and whose most distinguished
pupil, a personal acquaintance of his own, was then
working at Athens as a prolific writer. The whole tone
and character, moreover, of the Skepticism of the New
Academy betrays everywhere the presence of Stoic
influences. By the confidence of its assertions it
provokes contradiction and doubt, without its being
necessary to seek an explanation by improbable
conjectures as to the personal relations of Arcesilaus
and Zeno.
This connection of the New Academy with Stoicism can
be proved in the case of its first founder,
Arcesilaus. The doubts of this philosopher are
directed not only to knowledge derived from the
senses, but to rational knowledge as well. The
principal object of his attack was, however, the Stoic
theory of irresistible impressions; and in
overthrowing that theory Arcesilaus, it would seem,
believed he had exploded every possibility of rational
knowledge; for the Stoic appeal to the senses he
regarded as the only possible form of a theory of
knowledge, and the theories of Plato and Aristotle he
ignored altogether. Indeed, no peculiar arguments
against knowledge are referred to him. The old
skeptical arguments of Plato and Socrates, of
Anaxagoras, Empedocles, Democritus, Heraclitus, and
Parmenides, are repeated, all of which apply only to
the knowledge of the senses, and not to rational
knowledge. Nevertheless, Arcesilaus aimed at
overthrowing the latter along with the former. The
opinion that he only used doubt to prepare for or to
conceal genuine Platonism, is opposed to all credible
authorities. It appears, however, established that he
deemed it unnecessary to refute the theory of a
knowledge existing independently of the senses.
The Stoic arguments in favor of irresistible
impressions Arcesilaus met by asserting that an
intermediate something between knowledge and opinion,
a kind of conviction common to the wise and the
unwise, such as the Stoic comprehension, is
inconceivable; the wise man’s conviction is always
knowledge, that of the fool is always opinion. Going
then farther into the idea of comprehensible
perception, he endeavored to show that it
contained an internal contradiction; for to conceive
is to approve, and approval never applies to
sensation, but only to thoughts and general ideas.
Lastly, if the Stoics regarded force of conviction as
the distinctive mark of a true or irresistible
conception, and as belonging to it in distinction from
every other, the Sceptic rejoined that such
conceptions do not exist, and that no true conception
is of such a nature, but that a false one may be
equally irresistible. If no certainty of perception is
possible, no knowledge is possible. And since the wise
man--for on this point Arcesilaus agrees with the
Stoics--must only consider knowledge, and not opinion,
nothing remains for him but to abstain from all and
every statement, and to despair of any certain
conviction. It is therefore impossible to know
anything, nor can we even know for certain that we do
not know anything. It was quite in accordance with
this theory for Arcesilaus to lay down no definite
view in his lectures, but only to refute the views of
others. Even his disparaging remarks on dialectic,
supposing them to be genuine, are not at variance with
this conduct. He might consider the arguments of the
Stoics and the sophisms of the Megarians as useless,
whilst, at the same time, he was convinced that no
real knowledge could be attained by any other means.
He might even have inferred from their sterility, that
thought leads to truth quite as little as the senses.
There is no real difference between the result at
which he arrived and that of Pyrrho.
If opponents asserted that by denying knowledge all
possibility of action is denied, Arcesilaus declined
to accede to this statement. No firm conviction is, as
he maintained, necessary for a decision of the will;
for an action to come about a perception influences
the will immediately, leaving the question as to its
truth entirely out of sight. In order to act sensibly
we need no knowledge; for this purpose probability is
quite enough; any one can follow probability, even
though he is conscious of the uncertainty of all
knowledge. Thus probability is the highest standard
for practical life. We are but scantily informed how
Arcesilaus applied this principle to the sphere of
morals, but a few of his utterances are on record. All
bear witness to the beautiful spirit of moderation in
the moral theory of the Academy, which was otherwise
exemplified in his own life.
Comparing with the theory of Arcesilaus that which was
propounded by Carneades a century later, the same
leading features are found to be underlying; but the
points have been more carefully worked out, and the
theory placed on a wider footing. Of the immediate
followers of Arcesilaus it can only be stated that
they clung to their teacher. It may be presumed that
they did little in the way of expansion, since the
ancients are silent as to their labors; Carneades is
only mentioned as the continuer of the Academic
Skepticism The importance of Carneades is therefore
very great, whence he is in consequence called the
founder of the third or New Academy; and it is justly
great, witness the admiration which his talents called
forth among contemporaries and posterity, and the
flourishing condition in which he left his School.
Himself a pupil of Chrysippus, and resembling him in
tone of mind, Carneades expanded not only the negative
side of the Skeptical theory in all directions with an
acuteness entitling him to the first place among the
ancient Sceptics, but he was also the first to
investigate the positive side of Skepticism, the
doctrine of probability, and to determine the degrees
and conditions of probability. By his labors in both
ways he brought the philosophy of Skepticism to its
greatest scientific perfection.
As regards the negative side of these investigations,
or the refutation of dogmatism, the attacks of
Carneades were directed partly against the formal
possibility of knowledge, and partly against the chief
actual results of the knowledge of his day. In both
respects he had mainly to do with the Stoics, though
he did not confine himself to them.
To prove the impossibility of knowledge in general, he
appeals sometimes to experience. There is no kind of
conviction which does not sometimes deceive us;
consequently there is none which guarantees its own
truth. Going then further into the nature of our
notions, he argues, that since notions consist in the
change produced on the soul by impressions from
without, they must, to be true, not only furnish
information as to themselves, but also as to the
objects producing them. Now, this is by no means
always the case, many notions avowedly giving a false
impression of things. Hence the note of truth cannot
reside in an impression as such, but only in a true
impression. It is, however, impossible to distinguish
with certainty a true impression from one that is
false. For independently of dreams, visions, and the
fancies of madmen, in short, of all the unfounded
chimeras which force themselves on our notice under
the guise of truth, it is still undeniable that many
false notions closely resemble true ones. The
transition, too, from truth to falsehood is so
gradual, the interval between the two is occupied by
intermediate links so innumerable, and gradations so
slight, that they imperceptibly pass one into the
other, and it becomes impossible to draw a boundary
line between the two opposite spheres. Not content
with proving this assertion in regard to impressions
of the senses, Carneades went on to prove it with
regard to general notions based on experience and
intellectual conceptions. He showed that it is
impossible for us to distinguish objects so much alike
as one egg is to another; that at a certain distance
the painted surface seems raised, and a square tower
seems round; that an oar in the water seems broken,
and the neck-plumage of a pigeon assumes different
colors in the sun; that objects on the shore seem to
be moving as we sail by, and so forth; in all these
cases the same strength of conviction belongs to the
false as to the true impressions. He showed further
that this applies equally to purely intellectual
ideas; that many logical difficulties cannot be
solved; that no absolute distinction can be drawn
between much and little, in short between all
differences in quantity; and that it is the most
natural course in all such cases to follow Chrysippus,
and to avoid the dangerous inferences which may be
drawn by withholding judgment. Arguing from these
facts, Carneades concluded at first in regard to
impressions of the senses, that there is no such thing
as comprehensible perception in the
Stoic sense of the term, in other words, that no
perception contains in itself characteristics, by
virtue of which its truth may be inferred with
certainty. This fact being granted, the possibility is
in his opinion precluded of there residing in the
understanding a standard for the distinction of truth
from falsehood. The understanding--and this belief was
shared by his opponents--must derive its material from
the senses. Logic tests the formal accuracy of
combinations of thought, but gives no insight into
their import. Direct proofs of the uncertainty of
intellectual convictions are not therefore needed. The
same result may also be attained in a more personal
way, by raising the question, how individuals obtain
their knowledge. He can only be said to know a thing
who has formed an opinion respecting it. In the mean
time, until he has decided in favor of some definite
opinion, he has still no knowledge. And what
dependence can be placed on the judgment of one who
has no knowledge?
In these formal inquiries into the possibility of
knowledge, Carneades had chiefly to deal with the
Stoics, with whom he holds a common ground in his
appeal to the senses. The Stoics were also his chief
opponents in his polemic against the material results
of the dogmatic philosophy. Natural science having
throughout the period of the post-Aristotelian
philosophy been subordinated to ethics, ethics
likewise engaged more attention at the hands of
Carneades than science. In as far as he studied
Natural science, he appears to have been entirely
opposed to the Stoic treatment of the subject, and to
this circumstance we owe it, that better information
is forthcoming regarding his scientific, or rather his
theological, investigations than regarding his moral
views. The Stoic theories of God and of final causes
afforded ample scope for the exercise of his
ingenuity, and from the ground he occupied it was not
difficult for him to expose the weak points of that
theory. The Stoics had appealed in support of the
belief in God to the consensus theory of truth.
How close at hand was the answer, that the
universality of this belief was neither proved to
exist, nor as a matter of fact did it exist, but that
in no case could the opinion of an ignorant multitude
decide anything. The Stoics thought to find a proof of
divine providence in the manner in which portents and
prophecies come true. To expose this delusion, no very
expanded criticism of divination was necessary. Going
beyond this, Carneades proceeded to call in question
the cardinal point of the Stoic system--the belief in
God, the doctrine of the soul and reason of the
universe, and of the presence of design in its
arrangements. How, he asks, is the presence of design
manifested? Whence all the things which cause
destruction and danger to men if it be true that God
has made the world for the sake of man? If reason is
praised as the highest gift of God, is it not manifest
that the majority of men only use it to make
themselves worse than brutes? In bestowing such a gift
God must have been taking but little care of this
majority. Even if we attribute to man direct blame for
the misuse of reason, still, why has God bestowed on
him a reason which can be so much abused? The Stoics
themselves say that a wise man can nowhere be found.
They admit, too, that folly is the greatest
misfortune. How, then, can they speak of the care
bestowed by God on men, when, on their own confession,
the whole of mankind is sunk in tire deepest misery?
But allowing that the Gods could not bestow virtue and
wisdom upon all, they could, at least, have taken care
that it should go well with the good. Instead of this,
the experience of hundreds of cases shows that the
upright man comes to a miserable end; that crime
succeeds; and that the criminal can enjoy the fruits
of his misdeeds undisturbed. Where, then, is the
agency of Providence? The facts being entirely
different from what the Stoics suppose, what becomes
of their inferences? Allowing the presence of design
in the world, and granting that the world is as
beautiful and good as possible, why is it
inconceivable that nature should have formed the world
according to natural laws without the intervention of
God? Admitting, too, the connection of parts in the
universe, why should not this connection be the result
simply of natural forces, without a soul of the
universe or a deity? Who can pretend to be so
intimately acquainted with the powers of nature, as to
be able to prove the impossibility of this assumption?
Zeno argued that rational things are better than
things irrational, that the world is the best
possible, and must therefore be rational. Man, says
Socrates, can only derive his soul from the world;
therefore the world must have a soul. But what,
replies the Academician, is there to show that reason
is best for the world, if it be the best for us? or
that there must be a soul in nature for nature to
produce a soul? What man is not able to produce, that,
argues Chrysippus, must have been produced by a higher
being--by deity. But to this inference the same
objection was raised by the Academicians as to the
former one, viz. that it confounds two different
points of view. There may, indeed, be a Being higher
than man. But why must there needs be a rational
man-like Being? Why a God? Why not nature herself?
Nor did the argument seem to an Academician more
conclusive, that as every house is destined to be
inhabited, so, too, the world must be intended for the
habitation of God. To this there was the obvious
reply: If the world were a house, it might be so; but
the very point at issue is whether it is a house
constructed for a definite purpose, or whether it is
simply an undesigned result of natural forces.
Not content with attacking the conclusiveness of the
arguments upon which the Stoics built their belief in
a God, the skepticism of the Academy sought to
demonstrate that the idea of God itself is an
untenable one. The line of argument which Carneades
struck out for this purpose is essentially the same as
that used in modern times to deny the personality of
God. The ordinary view of God regards Him as an
infinite, but, at the same time, as a separate Being,
possessing the qualities and living the life of an
individual. To this view Carneades objected, on the
ground that the first assertion contradicts the
second; and argues that it is impossible to apply the
characteristics of personal existence to God without
limiting His infinite nature. Whatever view we may
take of God, we must regard Him as a living Being; and
every living being is composite, having parts and
passions, and is therefore destructible. Moreover,
every living being has a sense-nature. Far,
therefore, from refusing such a nature to God,
Carneades attributed to Him, in the interest of
omniscience, other organs of sense than the five we
possess. Now, everything capable of impressions
through the senses is also liable to change,
sensation, according to the definition of Chrysippus,
being nothing more than a change of soul. Every such
being must therefore be capable of pleasure and pain,
without which sensation is inconceivable. Whatever is
capable of change is liable to destruction; whatever
is susceptible to pain is also liable to
deterioration, pain being caused by deterioration, and
is also liable to destruction. As the capacity for
sensation, so too the desire for what is in harmony
with nature, and the dislike of what is opposed to
nature, belong to the conditions of life. Whatever has
the power of destroying any being is opposed to the
nature of that being, everything that lives being
exposed to annihilation. Advancing from the conception
of a living being to that of a rational being, all
virtues would have to be attributed to God as well as
bliss. But how, asks Carneades, can any virtue be
ascribed to God? Every virtue supposes an
imperfection, in overcoming which it consists. He only
is continent who might possibly be incontinent, and
persevering who might be indulgent. To be brave, a man
must be exposed to danger; to be magnanimous, he must
be exposed to misfortunes. A being not feeling
attraction for pleasure, nor aversion for pain and
difficulties, dangers and misfortunes, would not be
capable of virtue. Just as little could we predicate
prudence of a being not susceptible of pleasure and
pain; prudence consisting in knowing what is good,
bad, and morally indifferent. But how can there be any
such knowledge where there is no susceptibility to
pleasure or pain? Or how can a being be conceived of
capable of feeling pleasure, but incapable of feeling
pain, since pleasure can only be known by contrast
with pain, and the possibility of increasing life
always supposes the possibility of lessening it? Nor
is it otherwise with intelligence. He only is
intelligent who always discovers what will subserve
his purpose. If, however, he must discover it, it
cannot have been previously known to him. Hence
intelligence can only belong to a being who is
ignorant about much. Such a being can never feel sure
that sooner or later something will not cause his
ruin. He will therefore be exposed to fear. A being
susceptible of pleasure and exposed to pain, a being
who has to contend with dangers and difficulties, and
who feels pain and fear, must inevitably, so thought
Carneades, be finite and destructible. If, therefore,
we cannot conceive of God except in this form, we
cannot conceive of Him at all, our conception being
self-destructive.
There is yet another reason, according to Carneades,
why God cannot have any virtue; because virtue is
above its possessor, and there can be nothing above
God. Moreover, what is the position of God in regard
to speech? It was easy to show the absurdity of
attributing speech to Him, but to call him speechless
seemed also to be opposed to the general belief. Quite
independently, however, of details, the
inconceivableness of God appears, so soon as the
question is raised, whether the deity is limited or
unlimited, material or immaterial. God cannot be
unlimited; for what is unlimited is necessarily
immovable because it has no place, and soulless
because by virtue of its boundlessness it cannot form
a whole permeated by a soul; but God we ordinarily
think of both as moving and as endowed with a soul.
Nor can God be limited; for all that is limited is
incomplete. Moreover, God cannot be immaterial, for
Carneades, like the Stoics, held that what is
immaterial possesses neither soul, feeling, nor
activity. Neither can he be material, all composite
bodies being liable to change and destruction, and
simple bodies, fire, water, and the like, possessing
neither life nor reason. If, then, all, the forms
under which we think of God are impossible, His
existence cannot be asserted.
Easier work lay before the Sceptics in criticizing
polytheistic views of religion and their defense by
the Stoics. Among the arguments employed by Carneades
to overthrow them, certain chain-arguments are
prominent, by means of which he endeavored to show
that the popular belief has no distinctive marks for
the spheres of God and man. If Zeus is a God, he
argues, his brother Poseidon must likewise be one, and
if he is one, the rivers and streams must also be
Gods. If Helios is a God, the appearance of Helios
above the earth, or day, must be a God; and,
consequently, month, year, morning, midday, evening,
must all be Gods. Polytheism is here refuted by
establishing an essential similarity between what is
accepted as God and what is avowedly not a God. It may
readily be supposed that this was not the only proof
of the acuteness of Carneades’ reasoning.
Divination, to which the Stoics attached especial
importance, was vigorously assailed. Carneades proved
that no peculiar range of subjects belonged thereto,
but that in all cases which admit professional
judgment experts pass a better judgment than diviners.
To know accidental events beforehand is impossible; it
is useless to know those that are necessary and
unavoidable, nay, more, it would even be harmful. No
causal connection can be conceived of between a
prophecy and the ensuing realization If the Stoics met
him by pointing to fulfilled prophecies, he replied
that the coincidence was accidental, at the same time
declaring many such stories to be without doubt false.
Connected probably with these attacks on divination
was the defense by Carneades of the freedom of the
will. The Stoic fatalism he refuted by an appeal to
the fact that our decision is free; and since the
Stoics appealed in support of their view to the law of
causality, he likewise attacked this law. In so doing
his intention was not to assert anything positive
respecting the nature of the human will, but only to
attack the Stoic assertion, and if for his own part he
adhered to the old Academic doctrine of a free will,
he still regarded that doctrine as only probable.
Less information exists as to the arguments by which
Carneades sought to assail the current principles of
morality. Nevertheless, enough is known to indicate
the course taken by his Skepticism in relation
thereto. In the second of the celebrated speeches
which he delivered at Rome in the year 156 B.C., he
denied that there is such a thing as natural right:
all laws are only positive civil institutions devised
by men for the sake of safety and advantage, and for
the protection of the weak; and hence he is regarded
as foolish who prefers justice to interest, which
after all is the only unconditional end. In support of
these statements he appealed to the fact that laws
change with circumstances, and are different in
different countries. He pointed to the example of
great nations, such as the Romans, all of whom
attained to greatness by unrighteous means. He
impressed into his service the many casuistical
questions raised by the Stoics, expressing the opinion
that in all these cases it is better to commit the
injury which brings advantage--for instance, to murder
another to save one's own life--than to postpone
advantage to right, and hence inferred that
intelligence is a state of irreconcilable opposition
to justice.
This free criticism of dogmatic views could not fail
to bring Carneades to the same result as his
predecessors. Knowledge is absolutely impossible. A
man of sense will look at everything from all sides
and invariably withhold judgment, thus guarding
himself against error. And to this conviction he
clings so persistently that he altogether refuses to
listen to the objection that the wise man must be at
least convinced of the impossibility of any firm
conviction. The earlier Sceptics, far from attributing
on this ground an equal value to all notions, had not
dispensed with reasons for actions and thoughts. This
point was now taken up by Carneades, who, in
attempting to establish the conditions and degrees of
probability, hoped to obtain a clue to the kind of
conviction which might be still permitted in his
system. However much we may despair of knowledge, some
stimulus and groundwork for action is needed. Certain
things must therefore be assumed, from which the
pursuit of happiness must start. To these so much
weight must be attached that they are allowed to
decide our conduct, but we must be on our guard
against considering them to be true, or to be
something really known and conceived. Nor must we
forget that even the nature of true ideas is similar
to that of false ones, and that the truth of ideas can
never be known with certainty. Hence we should
withhold all assent, not allowing any ideas to be
true, but only to have the appearance of truth or
probability. In every notion two things need to be
considered, the relation to the object represented
which makes it either true or false, and the relation
to the subject who has the notion, which makes it seem
either true or false. The former relation is, for the
reasons already quoted, quite beyond the compass of
our judgment; the latter, the relation of a notion to
ourselves, falls within the sphere of consciousness.
So long as a notion seemingly true is cloudy and
indistinct, like an object contemplated from a
distance, it makes no great impression on us. When, on
the contrary, the appearance of truth is strong, it
produces in us a belief strong enough to determine us
to action, although it does not come up to the
impregnable certainty of knowledge.
Belief, however, like probability, is of several
degrees. The lowest degree of probability arises when
a notion produces by itself an impression of truth,
without being taken in connection with other notions.
The next higher degree is when that impression is
confirmed by the agreement of all notions which are
related to it. The third and highest degree is when an
investigation of all these notions results in
producing the same corroboration for all. In the first
case a notion is called probable; in the second
probable and undisputed; in the third probable,
undisputed, and tested. Within each one of these three
classes different gradations of probability are again
possible. The distinguishing marks, which must be
considered in the investigation of probability, appear
to have been investigated by Carneades in the spirit
of the Aristotelian logic. In proportion to the
greater or less practical importance of a question, or
to the accuracy of investigation which the
circumstances allow, we must adhere to one or the
other degree of probability. Although no one of them
is of such a nature as to exclude the possibility of
error, this circumstance need not deprive us of
certainty in respect to actions, provided we have once
convinced ourselves that the absolute certainty of our
practical premises is not possible. Just as little
should we hesitate to affirm or deny anything in that
conditional way which is alone possible after what has
been stated. Assent will be given to no notion in the
sense of its being absolutely true, but to many
notions in the sense that we consider them highly
probable.
Among questions about which the greatest possible
certainty is felt to be desirable, Carneades, true to
his whole position, gave a prominent place to
principles of morals; life and action being the
principal things with which the theory of probability
has to do. We hear, therefore, that he thoroughly
discussed the fundamental questions of Ethics, the
question as to the highest Good. On this subject he
distinguished six, or relatively four, different
views. If the primary object of desire can in general
only consist of those things which correspond with our
nature, and which consequently call our emotions into
exercise, the object of desire must be either
pleasure, or absence of pain, or conformity with
nature. In each of these three cases two opposite
results are possible: either the highest Good may
consist in the attainment of a purpose, or else in the
activity which aims at its attainment. The latter is
the view of the Stoics only, and arises from regarding
natural activity or virtue as the highest Good. Hence
the six possible views are practically reduced to
four, which taken by themselves, or else in
combination, include all existing views respecting the
highest Good. But so ambiguously did Carneades express
himself as to his particular preference of any one
view, that even Clitomachus declared he was ignorant
as to his real opinion. It was only tentatively and
for the purpose of refuting the Stoics, that he
propounded the statement that the highest Good
consists in the enjoyment of such things as afford
satisfaction to the primary impulses of nature.
Nevertheless, the matter has often been placed in such
a light as though Carneades had propounded this
statement on his own account; and the statement itself
has been quoted to prove that he considered the
satisfaction of natural impulses apart from virtue as
an end in itself. It is also asserted that he
approximated to the view of Callipho, which does not
appear to have been essentially different from that of
the older Academy. The same leaning to the older
Academy and its doctrine of moderation appears in
other recorded parts of the Ethics of Carneades. The
pain caused by misfortune he wished to lessen by
thinking beforehand of its possibility; and after the
destruction of Carthage he deliberately asserted
before Clitomachus that the wise man would never allow
himself to be disturbed, not even by the downfall of
his country.
Putting all these statements together, we obtain a
view not unworthy of Carneades, and certainly quite in
harmony with his position. That philosopher could not,
consistently with his skeptical principles, allow
scientific certainty to any of the various opinions
respecting the nature and aim of moral action; and in
this point he attacked the Stoics with steady
home-thrusts. Their inconsistency in calling the
choice of what is natural the highest business of
morality, and yet not allowing to that which is
according to nature a place among goods, was so
trenchantly exposed by him that Antipater is said to
have been brought to admit that not the objects to
which choice is directed, but the actual choice itself
is a good. He even asserted that the Stoic theory of
Goods only differed in words from that of the
Peripatetics; to this assertion he was probably led by
the fact that the Stoic morality appeals to nature
only, or perhaps by the theory therewith connected of
things to be desired and things to be eschewed. If
there were any difference between the two, Stoicism,
he thought, ignored the real wants of nature. The
Stoics, for instance, called a good a name a thing
indifferent; Carneades, however, drove them so much
into a corner because of this statement that they ever
after (so Cicero assures us) qualified their
assertion, attributing to a good name at least a
secondary value among things to be desired.
Chrysippus, again, thought to find some consolation
for the ills of life in the reflection that no man is
free from them. Carneades was, however, of opinion
that this thought could only afford consolation to a
lover of ill; it being rather a matter for sorrow that
all should be exposed to so hard a fate. Believing,
too, that man's happiness does not depend on any
theory of ethics, he could avow without hesitation
that all other views of morality do not go beyond
probability; and thus the statement of Clitomachus, as
far as it refers to a definite decision as to the
highest good, is without doubt correct. But just as
the denial of knowledge does not, according to the
view of Carneades, exclude conviction in general on
grounds of probability, no more does it in the
province of ethics. Here, then, is the intermediate
position which was attributed to him--a position not
only suggested by the traditions of the Academic
School, but remaining as a last resource to the
skeptical destroyer of systems so opposite as Stoicism
and the theory of pleasure. The inconsistency of at
one time identifying the satisfaction of natural
instincts with virtue, and at another time
distinguishing it from virtue, which is attributed to
Carneades, is an inconsistency for which probably
Cicero is alone responsible. The real meaning of
Carneades can only be that virtue consists in an
activity directed towards the possession of what is
according to nature, and hence that it cannot as the
highest Good be separated from accordance with nature.
For the same reason, virtue supplies all that is
requisite for happiness. Hence, when it is stated
that, notwithstanding his skepticism on moral
subjects, Carneades was a thoroughly upright man, we
have not only no reason to doubt this statement as to
his personal character, but we can even discern that
it was a practical and legitimate consequence of his
philosophy. It may appear to us inconsistent to build
on a foundation of absolute doubt the certainty of
practical conduct; nevertheless, it is an
inconsistency deeply rooted in all the skepticism of
post-Aristotelian times. That skepticism Carneades
brought to completeness, and in logically developing
his theory, even its scientific defects came to light.
For the same reason we may also give credit to the
statement that Carneades, like the later Sceptics,
notwithstanding his severe criticisms on the popular
and philosophic theology of his age, never intended to
deny the existence of divine agencies. On this point
he acted like a true Sceptic. He expressed doubts as
to whether anything could be known about God, but for
practical purposes he accepted the belief in God as an
opinion more or less probable and useful.
Taking all things into account, the philosophic
importance of Carneades and the School of which he was
the head cannot be estimated at so low a value as
would be the case were the New Academy merely credited
with entertaining shallow doubts, and Carneades’
theory of probabilities deduced from rhetorical rather
than from philosophical considerations. For the last
assertion there is no ground whatever; Carneades
distinctly avowed that a conviction resting on
probabilities seemed indispensable for practical needs
and actions. On this point he is wholly in accord with
all the forms of Skepticism, not only with the New
Academy, but also with Pyrrho and the later Sceptics.
He differs from them in the degree of accuracy with
which he investigates the varieties and conditions of
probability; but a question of degree can least of all
be urged against a philosopher. Nor should doubts be
called shallow which the ancients even in later times
could only very inadequately dissipate, and which
throw light on several of the deepest problems of life
by the critical investigations they occasioned. No
doubt, in the despair of attaining to knowledge at
all, and in the attempt to reduce everything to
opinion more or less certain, indications may be seen
of the exhaustion of the intellect, and of the
extinction of philosophic originality. Nevertheless it
must never be forgotten that the skepticism of the New
Academy was not only in harmony with the course
naturally taken by Greek philosophy as a whole, but
that it was pursued with an acuteness and a scientific
vigor leaving no doubt that it was a really important
link in the chain of philosophic development.
In Carneades this Skepticism attained its highest
growth. The successor of Carneades, Clitomachus, is
known as the literary exponent of the views taught by
Carneades. At the same time we hear of his being
accurately acquainted with the teaching of the
Peripatetics and Stoics; and although it was no doubt
his first aim to refute the dogmatism of these
Schools, it would appear that Clitomachus entered into
the connection of their doctrines more fully than is
usually the case with opponents. As to his
fellow-pupil, Charmidas (or Charmadas), one wholly
unimportant utterance is our only guide for
determining his views. For ascertaining the philosophy
of the other pupils of Carneades, nothing but the
scantiest fragments have been preserved. The statement
of Polybius that the Academic School degenerated into
empty subtleties, and thereby became an object of
contempt, may deserve no great amount of belief; but
it does seem probable that the School made no
important advance on the path marked out by himself
and Arcesilaus. It did not even continue true to that
path for very long. Not a generation after the death
of its most celebrated teacher, and even among his own
pupils, that eclecticism began to appear, the general
and simultaneous spread of which ushered in a new
period in the history of the post-Aristotelian
philosophy.
[Transcriber's Note: This text is
an online adaption of Eduard Zeller's book, taken
from the 1892 edition which is available here at
the Internet Archive. It is not a precise
transcription of the original book but a modified
version aimed at general readers, and as such, I
have eliminated footnotes, end notes, side notes,
the index, and sub-chapter headings, and I have
made minor spelling and grammatical changes. Also
since Zeller gives both a translation as well as
the original language of most of the Greek or
Latin terms he puts into the main text, I have
deleted the foreign terms to make for a smoother
reading experience (when Zeller does not provide a
translation, I have translated the original words
myself). Finally, there is a sentence in Chapter
17 which reads in the original: "With life every
feeling of evil ceases, and the time when we shall
no longer exist affects us just as little as the
time before we existed." I believe that in this
instance "life" is a misprint for "death" and have
changed the sentence accordingly.]